Using Cantor s Diagonal Method to Show ζ(2) is Irrational

Similar documents
Using Cantor s Diagonal Method to Show ζ(2) is Irrational

Vocabulary: Looking For Pythagoras

Cantor s Diagonal Argument for Different Levels of Infinity

Cardinality of Sets. Washington University Math Circle 10/30/2016

Chapter 3. Set Theory. 3.1 What is a Set?

The Size of the Cantor Set

Using Arithmetic of Real Numbers to Explore Limits and Continuity

UNIT-II NUMBER THEORY

MATHEMATICS 191, FALL 2004 MATHEMATICAL PROBABILITY Outline #1 (Countability and Uncountability)

EXAMPLE 1. Change each of the following fractions into decimals.

Mathematics Background

ELEMENTARY NUMBER THEORY AND METHODS OF PROOF

Topology and Topological Spaces

Rational Numbers: Multiply and Divide

Section 1.7 Sequences, Summations Cardinality of Infinite Sets

A B. bijection. injection. Section 2.4: Countability. a b c d e g

Section 2.4 Sequences and Summations

1.7 The Heine-Borel Covering Theorem; open sets, compact sets

Cardinality of Sets MAT231. Fall Transition to Higher Mathematics. MAT231 (Transition to Higher Math) Cardinality of Sets Fall / 15

ELEC-270 Solutions to Assignment 5

Material from Recitation 1

Continued Fractions: A Step-by-Step Tutorial, with User RPL Implementations

Divisibility Rules and Their Explanations

To illustrate what is intended the following are three write ups by students. Diagonalization

SPERNER S LEMMA MOOR XU

Grade 7/8 Math Circles Fall Nov.4/5 The Pythagorean Theorem

Repeat or Not? That Is the Question!

MITOCW watch?v=4dj1oguwtem

SETS. Sets are of two sorts: finite infinite A system of sets is a set, whose elements are again sets.

Source of Slides: Introduction to Automata Theory, Languages, and Computation By John E. Hopcroft, Rajeev Motwani and Jeffrey D.

A.1 Numbers, Sets and Arithmetic

Final Test in MAT 410: Introduction to Topology Answers to the Test Questions

A point is pictured by a dot. While a dot must have some size, the point it represents has no size. Points are named by capital letters..

Summary of Course Coverage

2 Review of Set Theory

Middle School Math Course 2

A Proof of Pythagorian s Theorem

CS 3512, Spring Instructor: Doug Dunham. Textbook: James L. Hein, Discrete Structures, Logic, and Computability, 3rd Ed. Jones and Barlett, 2010

3.1 Constructions with sets

Point-Set Topology 1. TOPOLOGICAL SPACES AND CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS

Lecture 3: Some Strange Properties of Fractal Curves

Topology Homework 3. Section Section 3.3. Samuel Otten

Comparing sizes of sets

Bulgarian Math Olympiads with a Challenge Twist

CSE 20 DISCRETE MATH. Fall

1. Let n be a positive number. a. When we divide a decimal number, n, by 10, how are the numeral and the quotient related?

Unit 2. Looking for Pythagoras. Investigation 4: Using the Pythagorean Theorem: Understanding Real Numbers

DISCRETE MATHEMATICS

On the computation of the n'th decimal digit of various transcendental numbers. Abstract

1 Counting triangles and cliques

Fifth Grade Math Rubric

function at the given point. Thus, for our previous example we would find that lim f(x) = 0

Section 1.2 Fractions

Chapter 1: Number and Operations

2. Functions, sets, countability and uncountability. Let A, B be sets (often, in this module, subsets of R).

THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS

Slides for Faculty Oxford University Press All rights reserved.

ELEMENTARY NUMBER THEORY AND METHODS OF PROOF

The strong chromatic number of a graph

Prime Time (Factors and Multiples)

Limitations of Algorithmic Solvability In this Chapter we investigate the power of algorithms to solve problems Some can be solved algorithmically and

ELEMENTARY NUMBER THEORY AND METHODS OF PROOF

Infinity and Uncountability. Countable Countably infinite. Enumeration

This Lecture. We will first introduce some basic set theory before we do counting. Basic Definitions. Operations on Sets.

NBT 4 Fluently add and subtract multi-digit whole number using the standard algorithm.

PITSCO Math Individualized Prescriptive Lessons (IPLs)

UNM - PNM STATEWIDE MATHEMATICS CONTEST XLI. February 7, 2009 Second Round Three Hours

COMPETENCY 1.0 UNDERSTAND THE STRUCTURE OF THE BASE TEN NUMERATION SYSTEM AND NUMBER THEORY

6th Bay Area Mathematical Olympiad

6c Lecture 3 & 4: April 8 & 10, 2014

Phil 320 Chapter 1: Sets, Functions and Enumerability I. Sets Informally: a set is a collection of objects. The objects are called members or

CSE 20 DISCRETE MATH. Winter

CSE 215: Foundations of Computer Science Recitation Exercises Set #4 Stony Brook University. Name: ID#: Section #: Score: / 4

Big Mathematical Ideas and Understandings

Vocabulary: Bits and Pieces III

Critical Numbers, Maximums, & Minimum

2017 SOLUTIONS (PRELIMINARY VERSION)

Lesson 9: Decimal Expansions of Fractions, Part 1

Math 5320, 3/28/18 Worksheet 26: Ruler and compass constructions. 1. Use your ruler and compass to construct a line perpendicular to the line below:

Solutions to First Exam, Math 170, Section 002 Spring 2012

3 Fractional Ramsey Numbers

1.2 Real Numbers. Objectives In this section, you will learn to:

Dr. Relja Vulanovic Professor of Mathematics Kent State University at Stark c 2008

Fractions. Dividing the numerator and denominator by the highest common element (or number) in them, we get the fraction in its lowest form.

12.1 Formulation of General Perfect Matching

Exercise 1.1. Page 1 of 22. Website: Mobile:

MATH 54 - LECTURE 4 DAN CRYTSER

Chapter 18 out of 37 from Discrete Mathematics for Neophytes: Number Theory, Probability, Algorithms, and Other Stuff by J. M. Cargal.

ELEMENTARY NUMBER THEORY AND METHODS OF PROOF

1.1 The Real Number System

Gwinnett County Public Schools Mathematics Fourth Grade Curriculum Map

TOPIC 2 DECIMALS (and INTRODUCTION TO FRACTIONS) WEEK 3

Repeating Decimals and Fractions

Nagual and Tonal Maths: Numbers, Sets, and Processes. Lukas A. Saul Oxford, England May, 2015

CSE 20 DISCRETE MATH WINTER

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Notes for Unit 1 Part A: Rational vs. Irrational

Order from Chaos. University of Nebraska-Lincoln Discrete Mathematics Seminar

Lemma (x, y, z) is a Pythagorean triple iff (y, x, z) is a Pythagorean triple.

Mini-Lectures by Section

Transcription:

Using Cantor s Diagonal Method to Show ζ(2) is Irrational Timothy W. Jones November 1, 2018 Abstract We look at some of the details of Cantor s Diagonal Method and argue that the swap function given does not have to exclude 9 and 0, base 10. We next review general properties of decimals and prove the existence of an irrational number with a modified version of Cantor s diagonal method. Finally, we show, with yet another modification of the argument, that ζ(2) is irrational. Introduction Cantor s diagonal method is typically used to show the real numbers are uncountable [1, 2]. Here is the reasoning. If the reals are countable they can be listed. In particular the decimal, base 10 versions of the real numbers in the open interval (0, 1) can be listed. List these numbers. Then starting with the upper left hand corner digit, construct, going down the upper left to lower right diagonal, a decimal not in the list. Use the following guide: if the decimal is 7 make your decimal 5 and if it is anything other than 7 make it 5. The number you construct is not in the list. This follows as the number constructed, per the construction, differs from every number in the list at least at one decimal place. The only exception to the uniqueness of these decimal representations occurs with rational numbers:.20 =.19, but because our swap function doesn t generate any 0s or 9s in the constructed number we are assured our constructed number is not in the list. Therefore the real numbers in (0, 1) are uncountable and a fortiori R is uncountable. 1

Could use 0 and 9 It is not difficult to see why even with a swap function involving 0 and 9, the construction still works. One must contrive a list of real numbers in (0, 1) in a particularly pernicious order. Every nth position after a point must be not 9 in order to build a string of all 9 s. If this could be true of a list, a number like.000009 could be the one constructed. If we observe.00001 in the list we have not constructed a number not it the list. But for any nth position there must be an infinite number with all possible digits, {0, 1,..., 9}, at that position. Hence, after working down the list, to say the mth number, there is a number further down that will block, in effect, any construction from being repeated. Every list will have a repetition of all combinations after any finite number in the list. By making the swap with numbers like 5 and 4 or 3 and 7 or any two that are not 9 and 0, we don t have to reason this out. What about convergence? Cantor s diagonal method does not address the convergence of the decimal representation of a real number constructed. Could it be all 5 s (.5) and hence converging to a rational number a number in the list. A combination of 4 s and 5 s that represent a infinitely repeating decimal? These observations are of no concern because the argument is that the number s representation is not in the list. Statements beyond this seem irrelevant. Of course if we suppose that ambiguity of representation is not allowed: only finite decimal representations are given of numbers like.5 and.49, then the infinite decimal we construct might be an excluded infinite decimal version of a number included in the list. This is when the use of not 9 and not 0 fix the situation fast. One could do a reductio ad absurdum argument. Suppose the constructed number converges to a number in the list, but the number in the list differs by at least one decimal point. So how close can.5554445454... get to say.555444454... they differ at the 7th place. The numbers must differ by at least.0000001. Another argument: decimal representations are unique, excluding representations like.59 =.6, but such a situation is impossible when neither 9 nor 0 are used in the swap function there are no 0s or 9s in the constructed number. But, all of these convulsive reasonings are superfluous: we can have 2

redundancy in the representation of the numbers. Both.50 and.49 can be included in the list: in fact, the list is succinctly and efficient given by all combinations of.x 1 x 2... with x k {0, 1,..., 9}. Constructing an irrational number Curiously, Cantor is most famous for his diagonal method and his construction of a transcendental number. The two are connected. He proved that all algebraic numbers are countable. If one lists all algebraic numbers then uses Cantor s diagonal method (henceforth CDM) shows there exists numbers that are not algebraic (not in the list): the number is a transcendental numbers [3]. It is rather curious that one is at once constructing a transcendental number, but ending up with just a number only in theory. You can t list all algebraic numbers. This is to be contrasted with Liouville s for real construction of a transcendental number years after Cantor s original proof that they must exist [3], in spirit, so to speak. It is also curious that no one, apparently till now has thought to use CDM to prove the existence of an irrational number. This is most likely because irrational numbers are a type of algebraic number and proofs that specific numbers like 2 are irrational are relatively easy. There would seem to be little point in proving the existence of irrational numbers using CDM or any other means. All of this said, here s the idea. List all the rational numbers in (0, 1) using base 10, or any other decimal base. Hardy gives a nice treatment of decimal bases in his Chapter 9 [3]. The list will include pure repeating decimals, finite decimals, and mixed decimals. In base 10, 1/3, 1/4, and 1/6 are examples of each respectively. Use the swap function that swaps or writes 4 if the number encountered using CDM is not 4 and 5 if the number encountered is 4. The number constructed is not in the list; it differs by at least one decimal point from all numbers listed. As all the numbers are all the rationals and the number generated is in (0, 1) it must be irrational. The number will be a non-repeating infinite decimal, an irrational. 3

Proving ζ(2) is irrational In Table 1 is a modified Cantor s Diagonal Table. The symbols D n 2 give single decimal points in base n 2. So, for example D 4 = {.1,.2,.3} in base 4. How to read the table: All previous columns (left to right) pertain to the new, right most partial. For example 1/4 + 1/9 + 1/16 is not in D 4, D 9, or D 16. So, like Cantor s diagonal method as applied to a list of base ten decimals, we build, not with a swap function, but with an addition, a number not in any decimal base given by a single decimal base n 2. +1/4 +1/9 +1/4 +1/4 +1/4 +1/4... +1/4 / D 4 +1/9 +1/9 +1/9 +1/9... +1/9 / D 9 +1/16 +1/16 +1/16 / D 16 +1/25 +1/25 / D 25 +1/36. / D 36 +1/(k 1) 2.. +1/k 2 / D k 2... Table 1: A list of all rational numbers between 0 and 1 modified to exclude them all via partial sums of ζ(2) 1. If this is true, can we conclude that z 2 = ζ(2) 1 must be irrational? Note: for any rational 0 < p/q < 1, (pq)/q 2 D q 2. Thus all partials with a last term of 1/q 2 can t be given with any single decimal base m 2 with m < q. Are we building a infinite series, like the infinite decimal of Cantor s original argument, that must be excluded from the list of all rationals (here-to-for all reals) and thus be irrational? Does the elimination element of Cantor s Diagonal Method force an irrational sum? Like CDM (in its original use) can we ignore the convergence point of the built infinite series? Well, to play it safe, can we prove the convergence point is not in our list? Consider the following use of the triangle inequality: let C x 4

be a single decimal rational in some D m 2, the best, meaning closest to z 2 in D m 2, then for all n (and m!!!) large enough, n 0 C 1 x < ɛ/2. (1) and So, in all cases, k 2 k=2 n 1 0 < k 2 z 2 < ɛ/2. k=2 0 < C x z 2 < ɛ. But this says z 2 is not rational. Note: any given rational number is repeated infinitely many times in D k n. For example, all rationals with denominators less than n are contained in D (n!) 2. The best approximation of z 2 in any D m 2 is never exact and later higher powers of m 2 are better. 5

The geometric series In Table 2, the same technique as given for z 2 is used to show 1 base 4 is not a finite decimal base 4. We know this, apart from Table 2, because the geometric series associated with this infinite, repeating decimal is 1 4 k = 1 3. k=1 +1/4 +1/4 +1/4 +1/4 +1/4... +1/4 +1/4 2 +1/4 2 +1/4 2 +1/4 2 +1/4 2... +1/4 2 / D 4 +1/4 3 +1/4 3 +1/4 3 +1/4 3... +1/4 3 / D 4 2 +1/4 4 +1/4 4 +1/4 4. / D 4 3 +1/4 5 +1/4 5. / D 4 4 +1/4 6. / D 4 5 +1/4 (k 1)2 +1/4 k2 / D 4 (k 1) 2... Table 2: A list of all finite decimals base 4. The decimal number.1, base 4 is generated by the sums. Looking again at Table 1, one can see why the technique shows that z 2 is irrational. In order for the partials to be converging to a rational, for every ɛ, there would have to be a rational that all partials with a given upper limit greater than n gets close to. But the partials always exceed, with their denominator, all {2, 4,..., n 2 } denominators. There are denominators further out from any given, fixed denominator that get consistently closer to such partials. Limits are unique, so the limit point can t be both approaching a previous finite decimal excluded earlier and some other later decimal. Another way to consider the situation is to note that approximations to limit points can never be limit points themselves. Finite decimals base 4 are all approximations to 1/3, some better, some worse, 6

none equal. In the case of ζ(2) 1 all rationals are approximations, some better, some worse, none perfect that is equal to ζ(2) 1. This means that ζ(2) is irrational. Yet from another perspective, each increase in the power of n 2, from n 2 to n 4 to n 6, in D n 2k yields a better approximation that supersedes the previous power. That is you really need to use the refinement of the ruler s tick marks to get a better approximation than the previous power of n yielded. This means that an infinite decimal is needed in all bases, all n 2 s, but, as the prime divisor of n and n 2 are the same, this implies that an infinite decimal is needed for z 2 in all bases. This is only possible if z 2 is irrational. Attempting the reasoning used in (1), we have 1/3 D 3 and it is fixed, unlike ζ(2) that requires differing C x rationals. For sufficient n, 1/3 will give a better approximation to the partial than any finite decimal in base 4. With ζ(2) there is no equivalent of 1/3 that is being approached. Evens and Bertrand s postulate It remains to show that partials escape the denominators of their terms: the set exclusions in the columns of Table 1 are correct. This is the juncture of the argument where the fact that all numbers (greater than 1, to a power of 2) are included in the sum of z 2. Every other number is even so the power of 2 in the denominator is always greater than 2 and so the reduced denominator always has at least 2 in it. For example, 1 4 + 1 9 + 1 16 = 61 144 and 61 144 + 1 25 61 + 1 144 = 25 144 25 shows how the pattern continues. Using Bertrand s postulate [3], we know there exists a prime p between n 2 /2 and n 2. Putting these two results together, n k=2 1 k 2 = a b, 7

where a/b is a reduced fraction with b > n 2. This established the set exclusions in the columns of Table 1 are correct. For details and general ζ(n), n 2, see [4]. Conclusion Cantor s diagonal method applied to show the existence of an irrational number and the proof given here for the irrationality of ζ(2) can be viewed as the same. The negations of set inclusions in Table 1 show that somewhere the decimal associated with the partial is not the same as those in each D k 2 set. As the union of all such sets give all the rationals the irrationality of ζ(2) follows. All decimal bases n 2 are replicated, including base 10 just like Cantor s original idea. You don t have to use a diagonal to ensure there is no replication: the wash just requires that as you go down the list, the construction can t equal any previously encountered number. References [1] T. M. Apostol, Mathematical Analysis, 2nd ed., Addison Wesley, Reading, Massachusetts, 1974. [2] R. Courant, H. Robbins, What is Mathematics, Oxford University Press, London, 1948. [3] G. H. Hardy, E. M. Wright, R. Heath-Brown, J. Silverman, and A. Wiles, An Introduction to the Theory of Numbers, 6th ed., Oxford University Press, London, 2008. [4] T.W. Jones, A Simple Proof that ζ(n) is Irrational (2017), available at available at http://vixra.org/abs/1801.0140 8