Lecture 1. 1 Notation

Similar documents
6c Lecture 3 & 4: April 8 & 10, 2014

TOPOLOGY, DR. BLOCK, FALL 2015, NOTES, PART 3.

THREE LECTURES ON BASIC TOPOLOGY. 1. Basic notions.

Cantor s Diagonal Argument for Different Levels of Infinity

Slides for Faculty Oxford University Press All rights reserved.

Math 170- Graph Theory Notes

Matching Algorithms. Proof. If a bipartite graph has a perfect matching, then it is easy to see that the right hand side is a necessary condition.

Ramsey s Theorem on Graphs

Fundamental Properties of Graphs

Notes for Recitation 8

Comparing sizes of sets

1.7 The Heine-Borel Covering Theorem; open sets, compact sets

[Ch 6] Set Theory. 1. Basic Concepts and Definitions. 400 lecture note #4. 1) Basics

HW Graph Theory SOLUTIONS (hbovik) - Q

Definition For vertices u, v V (G), the distance from u to v, denoted d(u, v), in G is the length of a shortest u, v-path. 1

AXIOMS FOR THE INTEGERS

Graph Theory. 1 Introduction to Graphs. Martin Stynes Department of Mathematics, UCC January 26, 2011

γ(ɛ) (a, b) (a, d) (d, a) (a, b) (c, d) (d, d) (e, e) (e, a) (e, e) (a) Draw a picture of G.

arxiv: v1 [math.co] 7 Dec 2018

Generell Topologi. Richard Williamson. May 6, 2013

Discrete Wiskunde II. Lecture 6: Planar Graphs

An Introduction to Graph Theory

Basics of Graph Theory

Infinite locally random graphs

Combinatorial Gems. Po-Shen Loh. June 2009

Homework Set #2 Math 440 Topology Topology by J. Munkres

Lecture 6: Graph Properties

MATHEMATICS 191, FALL 2004 MATHEMATICAL PROBABILITY Outline #1 (Countability and Uncountability)

8.1 Basic notions, facts and techniques

CSC Discrete Math I, Spring Sets

CS 3512, Spring Instructor: Doug Dunham. Textbook: James L. Hein, Discrete Structures, Logic, and Computability, 3rd Ed. Jones and Barlett, 2010

Cardinality of Sets MAT231. Fall Transition to Higher Mathematics. MAT231 (Transition to Higher Math) Cardinality of Sets Fall / 15

3 Fractional Ramsey Numbers

MATH 139 W12 Review 1 Checklist 1. Exam Checklist. 1. Introduction to Predicates and Quantified Statements (chapters ).

CHAPTER 2. Graphs. 1. Introduction to Graphs and Graph Isomorphism

Point-Set Topology 1. TOPOLOGICAL SPACES AND CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS

Discrete Mathematics Lecture 4. Harper Langston New York University

Lecture 20 : Trees DRAFT

On the Relationships between Zero Forcing Numbers and Certain Graph Coverings

Treewidth and graph minors

Bipartite Roots of Graphs

To illustrate what is intended the following are three write ups by students. Diagonalization

DO NOT RE-DISTRIBUTE THIS SOLUTION FILE

However, this is not always true! For example, this fails if both A and B are closed and unbounded (find an example).

CS 2336 Discrete Mathematics

Final Test in MAT 410: Introduction to Topology Answers to the Test Questions

Cardinality of Sets. Washington University Math Circle 10/30/2016

The clique number of a random graph in (,1 2) Let ( ) # -subgraphs in = 2 =: ( ) We will be interested in s.t. ( )~1. To gain some intuition note ( )

Lecture 22 Tuesday, April 10

The clique number of a random graph in (,1 2) Let ( ) # -subgraphs in = 2 =: ( ) 2 ( ) ( )

Topology and Topological Spaces

Pebble Sets in Convex Polygons

Key Graph Theory Theorems

Chapter Summary. Mathematical Induction Recursive Definitions Structural Induction Recursive Algorithms

arxiv: v1 [math.co] 4 Apr 2011

Topology I Test 1 Solutions October 13, 2008

2 Review of Set Theory

Graph Theory Questions from Past Papers

More reverse mathematics of the Heine-Borel Theorem

arxiv: v2 [math.co] 13 Aug 2013

Line Graphs and Circulants

Embedding a graph-like continuum in some surface

Matching Theory. Figure 1: Is this graph bipartite?

Lecture 11 COVERING SPACES

by conservation of flow, hence the cancelation. Similarly, we have

Senior Math Circles November 25, 2009 Graph Theory II

Material from Recitation 1

PACKING DIGRAPHS WITH DIRECTED CLOSED TRAILS

An Improved Upper Bound for the Sum-free Subset Constant

A GRAPH FROM THE VIEWPOINT OF ALGEBRAIC TOPOLOGY

A greedy, partially optimal proof of the Heine-Borel Theorem

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2013 Vazirani Note 7

Math 485, Graph Theory: Homework #3

Disjoint directed cycles

5 Graphs

.Math 0450 Honors intro to analysis Spring, 2009 Notes #4 corrected (as of Monday evening, 1/12) some changes on page 6, as in .

CS473-Algorithms I. Lecture 13-A. Graphs. Cevdet Aykanat - Bilkent University Computer Engineering Department

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

MAT 145: PROBLEM SET 4

Module 7. Independent sets, coverings. and matchings. Contents

Module 11. Directed Graphs. Contents

T. Background material: Topology

INTRODUCTION TO THE HOMOLOGY GROUPS OF COMPLEXES

Review of Sets. Review. Philippe B. Laval. Current Semester. Kennesaw State University. Philippe B. Laval (KSU) Sets Current Semester 1 / 16

On the number of distinct directions of planes determined by n points in R 3

A digital pretopology and one of its quotients

9.5 Equivalence Relations

FOUR EDGE-INDEPENDENT SPANNING TREES 1

Proof Techniques Alphabets, Strings, and Languages. Foundations of Computer Science Theory

Topology notes. Basic Definitions and Properties.

CS525 Winter 2012 \ Class Assignment #2 Preparation

DO NOT RE-DISTRIBUTE THIS SOLUTION FILE

A Reduction of Conway s Thrackle Conjecture

Math 443/543 Graph Theory Notes 5: Planar graphs and coloring

Partitioning Complete Multipartite Graphs by Monochromatic Trees

MATH 54 - LECTURE 4 DAN CRYTSER

Math 777 Graph Theory, Spring, 2006 Lecture Note 1 Planar graphs Week 1 Weak 2

Paths, Flowers and Vertex Cover

Lecture 2 - Graph Theory Fundamentals - Reachability and Exploration 1

4 Basics of Trees. Petr Hliněný, FI MU Brno 1 FI: MA010: Trees and Forests

Transcription:

Lecture 1 (The material on mathematical logic is covered in the textbook starting with Chapter 5; however, for the first few lectures, I will be providing some required background topics and will not be following the book. There are several references that you may find useful. For example, Kaye, Richard. The mathematics of logic, Cambridge University Press (2007). I am also making use of a set of notes originally developed by Alexander Kechris for the course Math 6c at Caltech.) 1 Notation We begin by describing some notation and conventions we will need throughout the course. N = {0, 1,... }. In set theory, it is customary to denote N by ω. A sequence is a function whose domain is either N or an initial segment of N (possibly empty). We identify natural numbers with their set of predecessors. So, if we say, for example, that a sequence has domain n N, what we mean is that its domain is {0, 1,..., n 1}. If we say that i k what we mean is that i < k. The length lh(s) of a sequence s is its domain if it is finite, and if it is N. We usually represent sequences as ordered tuples. Thus if s is a sequence with domain k, we will write (s(0), s(1),..., s(k 1)) for s. We will usually write s i rather than s(i), and omit parentheses and commas if there is no danger of ambiguity, so the sequence above can also be written as s 0 s 1... s k 1. The concatenation of two sequences s and t, where s is finite, is the sequence s t defined as follows: Let n = dom(s) and M = dom(t). Then s t is the sequence l that has domain n + M (if M = N then this is just N) and is given by: l(i) = s(i) for i < n. l(i) = t(i n) for n i, i n + M. We may write st for s t and si for s (i) if s and t are sequences and i is some object. A tree T is a set of finite sequences with the property that whenever s T and n < lh(s), then s n T. 1

The typical example of a tree is the (full) binary tree, also called the Cantor tree, 2 <N, consisting of all finite sequences of 0s and 1s. Trees are partially ordered in a natural way: Given sequences s, t, write s t to indicate that s is an initial segment of t. The root of a tree is the empty sequence,, which is an initial segment of any element (node) of the tree. If s t but s t, we write s t. Typically, I will imagine trees as growing downward: If s T, the successors of s are those t T such that s t. Its predecessors are those t such that t s; these are just the sequences s n for n < lh(s). The immediate successors of s are the successors of s of length 1 + lh(s). We can assign a stratification by levels to the tree T in a natural way; namely, the nodes of tree of length n form the n-th level of T. An infinite branch through a tree T is an infinite sequence s such that for all n, s n T. Intuitively, branches are paths through T. We denote by [T ] the set of all infinite branches through T. Thus [2 <N ] = 2 N is the set of all infinite sequences of 0s and 1s. This is usually called the Cantor set, since it can be naturally identified with Cantor s ternary subset of [0, 1]. In fact, this identification is a homeomorphism, when we give {0, 1} the discrete topology and {0, 1} N the product topology. Recall that in this topology a basic open set is one of the form for s 2 <N. N s = {x 2 N s x} 2 König s lemma A tree is infinite iff it has infinitely many nodes. It is finite branching iff each node has only finitely many immediate successors. 2

König s lemma is a very powerful tool that allows us to relate infinite and finite combinatorics, and we will use it frequently throughout the course. Its proof is remarkably simple. Lemma 1 (König) Let T be an infinite, finite branching tree. Then [T ]. Proof: By induction, we will identify for each n N a node s n in level n of T in such a way that 1. n < m implies that s n s m, and 2. The set of successors of s n is infinite. Condition (1) above allows us to form the infinite sequence s = n s n. By construction, s [T ], and this will give us the result we want. Condition (2) is used to ensure that we can keep the induction going. At stage 0 we simply set s 0 =. By hypothesis, T is infinite, so condition (2) is satisfied. Suppose s n has been defined. Let t 0,..., t k list all the immediate successors of s n. There are finitely many of them since T is finite branching, and at least one, since s n has infinitely many successors. Note also that a successor of s n is either a t i or a successor of t i. It follows that for some i k, t i has infinitely many successors. Let such t i be s n+1. This completes the induction. Exercise 1 Show that König s lemma is false if we omit the assumption that T is finite branching, even if we require that all levels of T be nonempty. Here is an application: Define a domino system to be a finite set D of domino types, i.e., unit squares (parallel to the axes) whose sides have been labeled. Note that we require that D is finite as part of the definition. For example, D could consist of the following domino types: 3

A tiling by D of the plane, or of a finite or infinite subset S of the plane, consist of a filling-in of the set S by dominoes of type in D so that adjacent dominoes have matching labels (no rotations are allowed). For example, the set D above can tile the plane by periodically repeating the pattern below: Theorem 2 For any domino system D, the following are equivalent: 1. D can tile the plane. 2. D can tile the upper right quadrant. 3. For each n = 1, 2,..., D can tile the n n square. Proof: Clearly, (1) implies (2), and (2) implies (3). We prove that (3) implies (1). Consider a system D that can tile all finite squares. Define a tree T as follows: At level 0 we have the empty sequence. At level n > 0, we have all tilings D of the (2n 1) (2n 1) square. Such a tiling is an immediate successor of a tiling of the (2n 3) (2n 3) square iff this smaller tiling occupies the center of the larger one. (It is straightforward to transform this labeling of nodes into a tree according to our conventions.) Note that T is infinite (by assumption (3)) and finite branching (since D is finite). By König s lemma, [T ], i.e., we can tile the odd-length squares in such a way that we can keep extending the tiling, thus covering the whole plane. This completes the proof. The above is a typical application of König s lemma. It allows us to replace an infinite problem (tiling the plane) with a series of finite and, perhaps, more approachable, problems. Other applications do the opposite: They allow us to extract information about finite combinatorics from result about infinite objects. We will see a few more examples next time, and throughout the course. 4

Lecture 2 We continue with the example of domino systems. Remark 3 There is no algorithm that determines whether a given D can tile the plane or not. Of course, for specific systems D, we usually can tell by ad hoc methods which one is the case. What the remark above indicates is that there is no uniform way of doing this. Corollary 4 There is a system D that can tile the plane, but not periodically. Proof: This is an example of a non-constructive proof. We will argue by contradiction, so that at the end we will know that there is such a system D, but we will have no information about what it looks like. Assume that every system that can tile the plane, can tile it periodically. Our goal is to build an algorithm that, given a system D, determines whether D can tile the plane or not, contradicting the remark above. Begin by enumerating all pairs (n, m) with n, m 1 as (n i, m i ). For example, we can set (n, m) = (n i, m i ) iff i = 2 n 1 (2m 1). Since D is finite, we can produce a listing of all possible tilings by D of the n 1 m 1 - rectangle, then of all the tilings by D of the n 2 m 2 -rectangle, and so on. Each of these listings is finite, since D is. At stage i we look at the tilings of n i m i. If it happens that there are no tilings, then the algorithm stops and outputs NO. If it happens that there is one such tiling that generates a periodic tiling of the plane, then the algorithm stops and outputs YES. Otherwise, stage i ends, and we go to stage i + 1. If D cannot tile the plane, then Theorem 2 gives us that D cannot tile some finite square, so the algorithm will eventually stop, and output NO. If D can tile the plane, our assumption is that it can do so periodically, and so the algorithm will eventually stop, and output YES. This shows that the algorithm always stops, and correctly identifies whether D tiles the plane or not. This is a contradiction. A typical application of König s lemma is in establishing compactness results. Theorem 5 The interval [0, 1] is compact. 5

Proof: Suppose a covering of [0, 1] by relatively open sets is given. We need to find a finite subcovering. There are only countably many rational numbers, so there are only countably many intervals with rational endpoints. Any relatively open subset of [0, 1] is the union of relatively open intervals with rational endpoints. It then suffices to show that if [0, 1] is covered by relatively open intervals with rational endpoints, then there is a finite subcovering. Say (a i, b i ), i N, are the intervals that form the covering; to ease notation, replace intervals of the form [0, a) with ( 1, a), intervals of the form (a, 1] with (a, 2), and [0, 1] with ( 1, 2). Define the dyadic intervals as those intervals of the form [ i I = 2, i + 1 ] n 2 n where 0 i < 2 n. In this case, we say that I is a dyadic interval of level n. We will show that for some n, each dyadic interval of level n is covered by some (a i, b i ). Otherwise, we can define a tree as follows: At level 1, we have [0, 1]. In general, at level n + 1 we have a collection of dyadic intervals of level n, none of which can be covered by some (a i, b i ). Given such a dyadic interval I, its immediate successors are those dyadic intervals of level n + 1 that are contained in I (so there are at most two of them) and such that they cannot be covered either by some (a i, b i ). Our assumption grants that, for all n, there is at least one dyadic interval of level n in the tree, so all levels of the tree are nonempty, and the tree is infinite. It is clearly finite branching so, by König s lemma, it has an infinite branch. This corresponds to a decreasing sequence I 0 I 1 I 2... of dyadic intervals, none of which is covered by some (a i, b i ). Moreover, I k has length 2 k for each k. It follows that n I n consists of exactly one point, let s call it x. Since the (a i, b i ) cover [0, 1], there is some i such that x (a i, b i ). But then I k (a i, b i ) for any sufficiently large k, and we have a contradiction. For our next example, define a graph G as a pair (V, G) where V is a set (of vertices) and G is a collection of unordered pairs of elements of V. We refer to the elements of G as the edges of G. If k is a positive integer, a k-coloring of G is a function f : V k such that whenever v 0, v 1 V are distinct, and {v 0, v 1 } G, then f(v 0 ) f(v 1 ). Exercise 2 Prove that a countable graph can be k-colored iff any finite subgraph can be k-colored. 6

This is true even for uncountable graphs, but something stronger than König s lemma is needed then. The celebrated four-color theorem of Appel and Haken states that any planar graph is 4-colorable. This is usually presented with the additional restriction that the graph is finite. Both versions are equivalent, by the remarks just mentioned. The following exercise is from Kaye s book mentioned above. Exercise 3 Define a k-sequence as a sequence with range contained in k, i.e., a sequence u 0 u 1... where each u i {0,..., k 1}. Such a sequence s is n-free iff there is no finite nonempty sequence x such that the concatenation x x... x of n copies of x appears as a contiguous block in s. 1. Show that there is no infinite 2-free 2-sequence. 2. Use König s lemma to show that there is an infinite 3-free 2-sequence iff there are arbitrarily long finite 3-free 2-sequences. Conclude the same about 2-free 3-sequences. 3. Let σ : 2 <N 2 <N be given by σ( ) =, σ(0) = 0 1, σ(1) = 1 0, and σ(u 0... u m ) = σ(u 0 )... σ(u m ). Let σ n (s) denote the n-th iterate of s, σ n (s) = σ(... (σ(s))... ) where there are n occurrences of σ. Show that σ n (0) is 3-free for each n. Conclude that there is an infinite 3-free 2-sequence. 4. Show that there is an infinite 2-free 3-sequence. In the examples above we have used König s lemma to deduce infinitary results from finite versions. The opposite is also possible. A typical and important example comes from Ramsey theory. Theorem 6 (Ramsey) Let G = (N, G) be a graph. Then there is an infinite X N such that either whenever a, b X and a b, then {a, b} G, or else whenever a, b X and a b, then {a, b} / G. Put another way, any graph on N either contains a copy of the infinite complete graph, or else it contains a copy of the infinite empty graph. Proof: Let x 0 = 0. Either there are infinitely many i > 0 such that {x 0, i} G or else there are infinitely many i > 0 such that {x 0, i} / G. Whichever the case is, let A 0 be the resulting infinite set and set x 1 = min(a 0 ). Now repeat, with x 1 in the role of x 0 and A 0 in the role of N : Either there are infinitely many i > x 1, i A 0, such that {x 1, i} G, or else there are infinitely many 7

such i such that {x 1, i} / G. Let A 1 be the resulting infinite set and set x 1 = min(a 1 ). Continue this way. This process generates a sequence x 0 < x 1 <... such that for all i, either: (0) i : For all k > i, {x i, x k } G, or else (1) i : For all k > i, {x i, x k } / G. There are only two cases, so for some j 2 there are infinitely many values of i such that (j) i holds. Then X = {x i : (j) i holds} is as wanted. An immediate application of König s lemma now gives us the following finitary result: Corollary 7 For all n there is a number N such that whenever a graph has N or more vertices, it contains either a copy of the empty graph on n vertices, or a copy of the complete graph on n vertices. Proof: Assume otherwise, and fix a counterexample n. Then, for each N, there is at least a graph on N vertices with no copy of either the empty graph on n vertices or the complete graph on n vertices. Put all these graphs in a tree by setting G as an immediate successor of G if G can be obtained from G by removing one vertex (and all the edges attached to it). This is an infinite finite branching tree, so König s lemma grants us the existence of an infinite branch, i.e., a sequence G 0, G 1, G 2,... of graphs such that, for all i: 1. G i+1 is obtained from G i by adding one vertex and some (maybe none) edges between this vertex and old vertices from G i, and 2. G i has no copy of the empty graph on n vertices, and no copy of the complete graph on n vertices. Consider the graph G obtained by taking the union of the graphs in this sequence. This is an infinite graph without a copy of either the empty or the complete graph on n vertices. But this is impossible, since Ramsey s theorem tells us that, in fact, G has a copy of the infinite empty graph, or the infinite complete graph. Corollary 7 can also be obtained by standard counting arguments. The disadvantage of invoking König s lemma (combinatorialists say invoking compactness ) is that the argument above gives us no clue as of how large N needs to be as a function of n. 8

In a few special cases, a deep result from logic (Herbrand s theorem) can be used to extract such functions from uses of König s lemma, but in general these arguments are nonconstructive. Typeset using LaTeX2WP. 9