Short proofs of coloring theorems on planar graphs

Similar documents
3-coloring planar graphs with four triangles

4-critical graphs on surfaces without contractible cycles of length at most 4

Correspondence coloring and its application to list-coloring planar graphs without cycles of lengths 4 to 8

PLANAR GRAPHS WITHOUT CYCLES OF LENGTH 4 OR 5 ARE (3, 0, 0)-COLORABLE

ON LOCAL STRUCTURE OF 1-PLANAR GRAPHS OF MINIMUM DEGREE 5 AND GIRTH 4

On Choosability with Separation of Planar Graphs with Forbidden Cycles

Lucky Choice Number of Planar Graphs with Given Girth

Near-colorings: non-colorable graphs and NP-completeness

Graphs with maximum degree 5 are acyclically 7-colorable

Star coloring planar graphs from small lists

Large Rainbow Matchings in Edge-Colored Graphs

Acyclic Edge Colorings of Graphs

A Note on Vertex Arboricity of Toroidal Graphs without 7-Cycles 1

Discrete Applied Mathematics

List Coloring Graphs

List colorings of K 5 -minor-free graphs with special list assignments

[8] that this cannot happen on the projective plane (cf. also [2]) and the results of Robertson, Seymour, and Thomas [5] on linkless embeddings of gra

ACYCLIC COLORING ON TRIPLE STAR GRAPH FAMILIES

Discharging and reducible configurations

A THREE AND FIVE COLOR THEOREM

On Acyclic Vertex Coloring of Grid like graphs

On Possible Counterexamples to Negami s Planar Cover Conjecture

This article appeared in a journal published by Elsevier. The attached copy is furnished to the author for internal non-commercial research and

Subdivisions of Graphs: A Generalization of Paths and Cycles

Disjoint directed cycles

Testing Maximal 1-planarity of Graphs with a Rotation System in Linear Time

Hamiltonian cycles in bipartite quadrangulations on the torus

Dominating Sets in Triangulations on Surfaces

An Investigation of the Planarity Condition of Grötzsch s Theorem

8 Colouring Planar Graphs

Properly Colored Paths and Cycles in Complete Graphs

Induced Forests in Planar Graphs

A step towards the Bermond-Thomassen conjecture about disjoint cycles in digraphs

Graphs and Combinatorics

Vertex decompositions of sparse graphs into an edgeless subgraph and a subgraph of maximum degree at most k

Acyclic Subgraphs of Planar Digraphs

Every planar graph is 4-colourable and 5-choosable a joint proof

Math 777 Graph Theory, Spring, 2006 Lecture Note 1 Planar graphs Week 1 Weak 2

K 4,4 e Has No Finite Planar Cover

The strong chromatic number of a graph

A simple algorithm for 4-coloring 3-colorable planar graphs

A note on Brooks theorem for triangle-free graphs

Note on list star edge-coloring of subcubic graphs

On Two Short Proofs About List Coloring Graphs

Acyclic edge-coloring of planar graphs: colors suffice when is large

Star coloring bipartite planar graphs

List edge-colorings of series-parallel graphs

The following is a summary, hand-waving certain things which actually should be proven.

The Grötzsch Theorem for the hypergraph of maximal cliques

Maximum 4-degenerate subgraph of a planar graph

The chromatic number of the square of subcubic planar graphs

On vertex-degree restricted subgraphs in polyhedral graphs

A new proof of 3-colorability of Eulerian triangulations

Prism-hamiltonicity of triangulations

ON THE EMPTY CONVEX PARTITION OF A FINITE SET IN THE PLANE**

Strong edge coloring of subcubic graphs

arxiv: v1 [math.ho] 7 Nov 2017

List Colouring Squares of Planar Graphs

Perfect Matchings in Claw-free Cubic Graphs

New Linear-Time Algorithms for Edge-Coloring Planar Graphs

MATH 350 GRAPH THEORY & COMBINATORICS. Contents

Acyclic Edge Colorings of Graphs

Vertex Decompositions of Sparse Graphs into an Edgeless Subgraph and a Subgraph of Maximum Degree at Most k

Every DFS Tree of a 3-Connected Graph Contains a Contractible Edge

Graph Coloring Problems

Non-zero disjoint cycles in highly connected group labelled graphs

Simultaneous Diagonal Flips in Plane Triangulations

Weak Dynamic Coloring of Planar Graphs

FOUR EDGE-INDEPENDENT SPANNING TREES 1

EDGE MAXIMAL GRAPHS CONTAINING NO SPECIFIC WHEELS. Jordan Journal of Mathematics and Statistics (JJMS) 8(2), 2015, pp I.

Part II. Graph Theory. Year

Subdivided graphs have linear Ramsey numbers

arxiv: v4 [math.co] 6 Dec 2015

Ma/CS 6b Class 26: Art Galleries and Politicians

Whitney s theorem for 2-regular planar digraphs

Edge coloring ofgraphs with small average degrees

On Galvin orientations of line graphs and list-edge-colouring

Extremal functions for rooted minors

An upper bound for the chromatic number of line graphs

Math 776 Graph Theory Lecture Note 1 Basic concepts

Some Elementary Lower Bounds on the Matching Number of Bipartite Graphs

Vertex-Colouring Edge-Weightings

Totally odd subdivisions and parity subdivisions: Structures and Coloring

Acyclic Edge Colouring of 2-degenerate Graphs

Homomorphisms of Signed Graphs

Do triangle-free planar graphs have exponentially many 3-colorings?

Coloring edges and vertices of graphs without short or long cycles

VIZING S THEOREM AND EDGE-CHROMATIC GRAPH THEORY. Contents

ADJACENCY POSETS OF PLANAR GRAPHS

Math 443/543 Graph Theory Notes 11: Graph minors and Kuratowski s Theorem

arxiv: v1 [math.co] 4 Apr 2011

Which n-venn diagrams can be drawn with convex k-gons?

On the structure of 1-planar graphs

Line Graphs and Circulants

CLAW-FREE 3-CONNECTED P 11 -FREE GRAPHS ARE HAMILTONIAN

Discrete Wiskunde II. Lecture 6: Planar Graphs

arxiv: v1 [cs.dm] 13 Apr 2012

Open Neighborhood Chromatic Number Of An Antiprism Graph

Potential Bisections of Large Degree

A Reduction of Conway s Thrackle Conjecture

Transcription:

Short proofs of coloring theorems on planar graphs Oleg V. Borodin Alexandr V. Kostochka Bernard Lidický Matthew Yancey February 28, 20 Abstract A recent lower bound on the number of edges in a k-critical n- vertex graph by Kostochka and Yancey yields a half-page proof of the celebrated Grötzsch Theorem that every planar triangle-free graph is -colorable. In this paper we use the same bound to give short proofs of other known theorems on -coloring of planar graphs, among whose is the Grünbaum-Aksenov Theorem that every planar with at most three triangles is -colorable. We also prove the new result that every graph obtained from a triangle-free planar graph by adding a vertex of degree at most four is -colorable. Sobolev Institute of Mathematics and Novosibirsk State University, Novosibirsk 60090, Russia E-mail: brdnoleg@math.nsc.ru. Research of this author is supported in part by grants 2-0-00448 and 2-0-006 of the Russian Foundation for Basic Research. University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign, Urbana, IL 680, USA and Sobolev Institute of Mathematics, Novosibirsk 60090, Russia. E-mail: kostochk@math.uiuc.edu. Research of this author is supported in part by NSF grant DMS-0965587. University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign, Urbana, IL 680, USA, E-mail: lidicky@illinois.edu University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign, Urbana, IL 680, USA, E-mail: yancey@illinois.edu. Research of this author is partially supported by the Arnold O. Beckman Research Award of the University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign and from National Science Foundation grant DMS 08-844 EMSW2-MCTP: Research Experience for Graduate Students.

Introduction Graphs considered in this paper are simple, i.e., without loops or parallel edges. For a graph G, the set of its vertices is denoted by V (G) and the set of its edges by E(G). An embedding σ of a graph G = (V, E) in a surface Σ is an injective mapping of V to a point set P in Σ and E to non-self-intersecting curves in Σ such that (a) for all v V and e E, σ(v) is never an interior point of σ(e), and σ(v) is an endpoint of σ(e) if and only if v is a vertex of e, and (b) for all e, h E, σ(h) and σ(e) can intersect only in vertices of P. A graph is planar if it has an embedding in the plane. A graph with its embedding in the (projective) plane is a (projective) plane graph. A cycle in a graph embedded in Σ is contractible if it splits Σ into two surfaces where one of them is homeomorphic to a disk. A (proper) coloring ϕ of a graph G is a mapping from V (G) to a set of colors C such that ϕ(u) ϕ(v) whenever uv E(G). A graph G is k- colorable if there exists a coloring of G using at most k colors. A graph G is k-critical if G is not (k )-colorable but every proper subgraph of G is (k )-colorable. By definition, if a graph G is not (k )-colorable then it contains a k-critical subgraph. Dirac [2] asked to determine the minimum number of edges in a k- critical graph. Ore conjectured [22] that an upper bound obtained from Hajós construction is tight. More details about Ore s conjecture can be found in [8][Problem 5.] and in [20]. Recently, Kostochka and Yancey [20] confirmed Ore s conjecture for k = 4 and showed that the conjecture is tight in infinitely many cases for every k 5. In [9] they gave a 2.5-page proof of the case k = 4: Theorem ([9]). If G is a 4-critical n-vertex graph then E(G) 5n 2. Theorem yields a half-page proof [9] of the celebrated Grötzsch Theorem [4] that every planar triangle-free graph is -colorable. This paper presents short proofs of some other theorems on -coloring of graphs close to planar. Most of these results are generalizations of Grötzsch Theorem. Examples of such generalizations are results of Aksenov [2] and Jensen and Thomassen [7]. 2

Theorem 2 ([2, 7]). Let G be a triangle-free planar graph and H be a graph such that G = H h for some edge h of H. Then H is -colorable. Theorem ([7]). Let G be a triangle-free planar graph and H be a graph such that G = H v for some vertex v of degree. Then H is -colorable. We show an alternative proof of Theorem 2 and give a strengthening of Theorem. Theorem 4. Let G be a triangle-free planar graph and H be a graph such that G = H v for some vertex v of degree 4. Then H is -colorable. Theorems 2 and 4 yield a short proof of the following extension theorem that was used by Grötzsch [4]. Theorem 5. Let G be a triangle-free planar graph and F be a face of G of length at most 5. Then each -coloring of F can be extended to a -coloring of G. An alternative statement of Theorem 2 is that each coloring of two vertices of a triangle-free planar graph G by two different colors can be extended to a -coloring of G. Aksenov et al. [] extended Theorem 2 by showing that each proper coloring of each induced subgraph on two vertices of G extends to a -coloring of G. Theorem 6 ([]). Let G be a triangle-free planar graph. Then each coloring of two non-adjacent vertices can be extended to a -coloring of G. We show a short proof of Theorem 6. Another possibility to strengthen Grötzsch s Theorem is to allow at most three triangles. Theorem 7 ([, 4, 5]). Let G be a planar graph containing at most three triangles. Then G is -colorable. The original proof by Grünbaum [5] was incorrect and a correct proof was provided by Aksenov []. A simpler proof was given by Borodin [4], but our proof is significantly simpler. Youngs [0] constructed triangle-free graphs in the projective plane that are not -colorable. Thomassen [25] showed that if G is embedded in the projective plane without contractible cycles of length at most 4 then G is -colorable. We slightly strengthen the result by allowing two contractible 4-cycles or one contractible -cycle.

Theorem 8. Let G be a graph embedded in the projective plane such that the embedding has at most two contractible cycles of length 4 or one contractible cycle of length three such that all other cycles of length at most 4 are noncontractible. Then G is -colorable. It turned out that restricting the number of triangles is not necessary. Havel conjectured [6] that there exists a constant c such that if every pair of triangles in a planar graph G is at distance at least c then G is -colorable. The conjecture was proven true by Dvořák, Král and Thomas []. Without restriction on triangles, Steinberg conjectured [2] that every planar graph without 4- and 5-cycles is -colorable. Erdős suggested to relax the conjecture and asked for the smallest k such that every planar graphs without cycles of length 4 to k is -colorable. The best known bound for k is 7 [9]. A cycle C is triangular if it is adjacent to a triangle other than C. In [6], it is proved that every planar graph without triangular cycles of length from 4 to 7 is -colorable, which implies all results in [7, 8, 9, 0,, 2, 26, 27, 28, 29]. We present the following result in the direction towards Steinberg s conjecture with a Havel-type constraint on triangles. As a free bonus, the graph can be in the projective plane instead of the plane. Theorem 9. Let G be a 4-chromatic projective planar graph where every vertex is in at most one triangle. Then G contains a cycle of length 4,5 or 6. There are numerous other results on the Three Color Problem in the plane. See a recent survey [5] or a webpage maintained by Montassier http: //janela.lirmm.fr/~montassier/index.php?n=site.threecolorproblem. The next section contains proofs of the presented theorems and Section contains constructions showing that some of the theorems are best possible. 2 Proofs Identification of non-adjacent vertices u and v in a graph G results in a graph G obtained from G {u, v} by adding a new vertex x adjacent to every vertex that is adjacent to at least one of u and v. The following lemma is a well-known tool to reduce the number of 4-faces. We show its proof for the completeness. 4

z z x v 0 v y v 0 v v v 2 v v 2 x = y (a) (b) Figure : Triangle adjacent to a 4-face in Lemma 0. Lemma 0. Let G be a plane graph and F = v 0 v v 2 v be a 4-face in G such that v 0 v 2, v v E(G). Let G i be obtained from G by identifying v i and v i+2 where i {0, }. If the number of triangles increases in both G 0 and G then there exists a triangle v i v i+ z for some z V (G) and i {0,, 2, }. Moreover, G contains vertices x and y not in F such that v i+ zxv i and v i zyv i+2 are paths in G. Indices are modulo 4. See Figure. Proof. Let G, F, G 0 and G be as in the statement of the lemma. Since the number of triangles increases in G 0 there must be a path v 0 zyv 2 in G where z, y F. Similarly, a new triangle in G implies a path v wxv in G where w, x F. By the planarity of G, {z, y} and {w, x} are not disjoint. Without loss of generality assume z = w. This results in triangle v 0 v z and paths v zxv and v 0 zyv 2. Note that x and y do not have to be distinct. See Figure (b). Proof of Theorem 2. Let H be a smallest counterexample and G be a plane triangle-free graph such that G = H h for some edge h = uv. Let H have n vertices and e edges and G have f faces. Note that G has n vertices and e edges. By the minimality of H, H is 4-critical. So Theorem implies e 5n 2. CASE : G has at most one 4-face. Then 5f 2(e ) and hence f (2e )/5. By this and Euler s Formula n (e ) + f = 2 applied on G we have 5n e + 5, i.e., e 5n 4. This contradicts Theorem. 5

CASE 2: Every 4-face of G contains both u and v and there are at least two such 4-faces F x = ux vx 2 and F y = uy vy 2. If there exists z {x, x 2 } {y, y 2 } then z has degree two in G which contradicts the 4-criticality of G. Let G be obtained from G by identification of x and x 2 into a new vertex x. If G is not triangle-free then there is a path P = x q q 2 x 2 in G where q, q 2 F x. Since P must cross uy v and uy 2 v, we may assume that y = q and y 2 = q 2. However, y y 2 E(G). This contradicts the existence of P. Hence G is triangle-free. Let H = G + h. By the minimality of H, there exists a -coloring ϕ of H. This contradicts that H is not 4-colorable since ϕ can be extended to H by letting ϕ(x ) = ϕ(x 2 ) = ϕ(x). CASE : G has a 4-face F with vertices v 0 v v 2 v in the cyclic order where h is neither v 0 v 2 nor v v. Since G is triangle-free, neither v 0 v 2 nor v v are edges of G. Lemma 0 implies that either v 0 and v 2 or v and v can be identified without creating a triangle. Without loss of generality assume that G, obtained by from G identification of v 0 and v 2 to a new vertex v, is triangle-free. Let H = G + h. By the minimality of H, there is a -coloring ϕ of H. The -coloring ϕ can be extended to H by letting ϕ(v 0 ) = ϕ(v 2 ) = ϕ(v) which contradicts the 4-criticality of H. Proof of Theorem 4. Let H be a smallest counterexample and G be a plane triangle-free graph such that G = H v for some vertex v of degree 4. Let H have n vertices and e edges and G have f faces. Then G has n vertices and e 4 edges. By minimality, H is 4-critical. So Theorem implies e 5n 2. CASE : G has no 4-faces. Then 5f 2(e 4) and hence f 2(e 4)/5. By this and Euler s Formula (n ) (e 4) + f = 2 applied to G, we have 5n e 8 5, i.e., e 5n. This contradicts Theorem. CASE 2: G has a 4-face F with vertices v 0 v v 2 v in the cyclic order. Since G is triangle-free, neither v 0 v 2 nor v v are edges of G and Lemma 0 applies. Without loss of generality assume that G 0 obtained from G by identification of v 0 and v 2 is triangle-free. By the minimality of H, the graph obtained from H by identification of v 0 and v 2 satisfies the assumptions of the theorem and hence has a -coloring. Then H also has a -coloring, a contradiction. Proof of Theorem 5. Let the -coloring of F be ϕ. CASE : F is a 4-face where v 0 v v 2 v are its vertices in cyclic order. CASE.: ϕ(v 0 ) = ϕ(v 2 ) and ϕ(v ) = ϕ(v ). Let G be obtained from G by adding a vertex v adjacent to v 0, v, v 2 and v. Since G satisfies the 6

assumptions of Theorem 4, there exists a -coloring ϱ of G. In any such -coloring, ϱ(v 0 ) = ϱ(v 2 ) and ϱ(v ) = ϱ(v ). Hence by renaming the colors in ϱ we obtain an extension of ϕ to a -coloring of G. By symmetry, the other subcase is the following. CASE.2: ϕ(v 0 ) = ϕ(v 2 ) and ϕ(v ) ϕ(v ). Let G be obtained from G by adding the edge v v. Since G satisfies the assumptions of Theorem 2, there exists a -coloring ϱ of G. In any such -coloring, ϱ(v ) ϱ(v ) and hence ϱ(v 0 ) = ϱ(v 2 ). By renaming the colors in ϱ we obtain an extension of ϕ to a -coloring of G. CASE 2: F is a 5-face where v 0 v v 2 v v 4 are its vertices in cyclic order. Observe that up to symmetry there is just one coloring of F. So without loss of generality assume that ϕ(v 0 ) = ϕ(v 2 ) and ϕ(v ) = ϕ(v ). Let G be obtained from G by adding a vertex v adjacent to v 0, v, v 2 and v. Since G satisfies the assumptions of Theorem 4, there exists a -coloring ϱ of G. Note that in any such -coloring ϱ(v 0 ) = ϱ(v 2 ) and ϱ(v ) = ϱ(v ). Hence by renaming the colors in ϱ we can extend ϕ to a -coloring of G. Proof of Theorem 6. Let G be a smallest counterexample and let u, v V (G) be the two non-adjacent vertices colored by ϕ. If ϕ(u) ϕ(v) then the result follows from Theorem 2 by considering graph obtained from G by adding the edge uv. Hence assume that ϕ(u) = ϕ(v). CASE : G has at most two 4-faces. Let H be a graph obtained from G by identification of u and v. Any -coloring of H yields a -coloring of G where u and v are colored the same. By this and the minimality of G we conclude that H is 4-critical. Let G have e edges, n + vertices and f faces. Since G is planar 5f 2 2e. By this and Euler s formula, 2e + 2 + 5(n + ) 5e 0 and hence e (5n )/, a contradiction to Theorem. CASE 2: G has at least three 4-faces. Let F be a 4-face with vertices v 0 v v 2 v in the cyclic order. Since G is triangle-free, neither v 0 v 2 nor v v are edges of G. Hence Lemma 0 applies. Without loss of generality let G 0 from Lemma 0 be triangle-free. By the minimality of G, G 0 has a -coloring ϕ where ϕ(u) = ϕ(v) unless uv E(G 0 ). Since uv E(G), without loss of generality v 0 = u and v 2 v E(G). Moreover, the same cannot happen to G from Lemma 0, hence G contains a triangle. Thus G contains a path v q q 2 v where q, q 2 F, and G also 7

v q u = v 0 v 2 v v q 2 Figure 2: Configuration from Theorem 6. contains a 5-cycle C = uv q q 2 v (see Figure 2). By Theorem 5, C is a 5-face. Hence u is a 2-vertex incident with only one 4-face. By symmetric argument with a different 4-face, v is also a 2-vertex incident with one 4-face and 5-face. However, G has at least one more 4-face where identification of vertices does not result in the edge uv, a contradiction to the minimality of G. Proof of Theorem 8. Let G be a minimal counterexample with e edges, n vertices and f faces. By minimality, G is a 4-critical and has at most two 4-faces or one -face. From embedding, 5f 2 2e. By Euler s formula, 2e+2+5n 5e 5. Hence e (5n )/, a contradiction to Theorem. Borodin used in his proof of Theorem 7 a technique called portionwise coloring. We avoid it and build the proof on the previous results arising from Theorem. Proof of Theorem 7. Let G be a smallest counterexample. By minimality, G is 4-critical and every triangle is a face. By Theorem 5 for every separating 4-cycle and 5-cycle C, both the interior and exterior of C contain triangles. CASE : G has no 4-faces. Then 5f 6 2e and by Euler s Formula e + 6 + 5n 5e 0, i.e., e 5n 4. This contradicts Theorem. CASE 2: G has a 4-face F = v 0 v v 2 v such that v 0 v 2 E(G). By the minimality, v 0 v v 2 and v 0 v v 2 are both -faces and hence G has 4 vertices, 5 edges and it is -colorable. CASE : For every 4-face F = v 0 v v 2 v, neither v 0 v 2 nor v v are edges of G. By Lemma 0, there exist paths v 0 zyv 2 and v zxv. CASE.: G contains a -prism with one of its 4-cycles being a 4-face. We may assume that this face is our F and x = y, see Figure (b). Theorem 5 implies that one of zv 0 v x, zv v 2 x is a 4-face. Without loss of generality 8

assume that zv v 2 x is a 4-face. Let G 0 be obtained from G by identification of v 0 and v 2 to a new vertex v. Since G 0 is not -colorable, it contains a 4-critical subgraph G 0. Note that G 0 contains triangle xvz that is not in G but v 0 v z is not in G 0 since d(v ) = 2 in G 0. By the minimality of G, there exists another triangle T that is in G 0 but not in G. By planarity, x T. Hence there is a vertex w v such that v 0 and x are neighbors of w. By considering identification of v and v and by symmetry, we may assume that there is a vertex w 2 v 0 such that v and z are neighbors of w 2. By planarity we conclude that w = w 2. This contradicts the fact that G has at most three triangles. Therefore G is -prism-free. CASE.2: G contains no -prism with one of its 4-cycles being a 4-face. Then x y, see Figure (a). If v 0 x E(G) then G v 0 is triangle-free and Theorem gives a -coloring of G, a contradiction. Similarly, v y E(G). Suppose that zv 0 v x if a 4-face. Let G be obtained from G v 0 by adding edge xv. If the number of triangles in G is at most three, then G has a -coloring ϕ by the minimality of G. Let ϱ be a -coloring of G such that ϱ(v) = ϕ(v) if v V (G ) and ϱ(v 0 ) = ϕ(x). Since the neighbors of v 0 in G are neighbors of x in G, ϱ is a -coloring, a contradiction. Therefore G has at least four triangles and hence G contains a vertex t z adjacent to v and x. Since v y E(G), the only possibility is t = v 2. Having edge xv 2 results in a -prism being a subgraph of G which is already excluded. Hence zv 0 v x is not a face and by symmetry zv v 2 y is not a face either. Since neither zv 0 v x nor zv v 2 y is a face, each of them contains a triangle in its interior. Since we know the location of all three triangles, Theorem 5 implies that zyv 2 v x is a 5-face. It also implies that the common neighbors of z and v are exactly v 0 and x, and the common neighbors of z and v 2 are exactly v and y. Without loss of generality, let zyv 2 v x be the outer face of G. Let H be obtained from the 4-cycle zv 0 v x and its interior by adding edge zv. The edge zv is in only two triangles, and there is only one triangle in the interior of the 4-cycle. Hence by the minimality of G, there exists a -coloring ϕ of H. Let H 2 be obtained from the 4-cycle zv v 2 y and its interior by adding edge zv 2. By the same argument as for H, there is a -coloring of ϕ 2 of H 2. Rename the colors in ϕ 2 so that ϕ (z) = ϕ 2 (z), ϕ (v 0 ) = ϕ 2 (v 2 ) and ϕ (v ) = ϕ 2 (v ). Then ϕ ϕ 2 is a -coloring of G, a contradiction. Proof of Theorem 9. Let G be a 4-chromatic projective plane graph where 9

Figure : First three 4-critical graphs from the family described by Thomas and Walls [24]. every vertex is in at most one triangle and let G be 4-,5- and 6-cycle free. Then G contains a 4-critical subgraph G. Let G have e edges, n vertices and f faces. Since G is also 4-,5- and 6-cycle-free and every vertex is in at most one triangle, we get f n+ 2e n. By Eulers formula, 7n+6e n+2n 2e 7 2. Hence e 5n/ 2/5, a contradiction to Theorem. Tightness This section shows examples where Theorems 2,4,5,6,7, and 8 are tight. Theorem 2 is best possible because there exists an infinite family [24] of 4-critical graphs that become triangle-free and planar after removal of just two edges. See Figure. Moreover, the same family shows also the tightness of Theorem 7, since the construction has exactly four triangles. Aksenov [] showed that every plane graph with one 6-face F and all other faces being 4-faces has no -coloring in which the colors of vertices of F form the sequence (, 2,,, 2, ). This implies that Theorem 5 is best possible. It also implies that Theorems 4 and 6 are best possible. See Figure 4 for constructions where coloring of three vertices or an extra vertex of degree 5 force a coloring (, 2,,, 2, ) of a 6-cycle. Theorem 8 is best possible because there exist embeddings of K 4 in the projective plane with three 4-faces or with two -faces and one 6-face. 0

2 2 (a) (b) (c) (d) Figure 4: Coloring of three vertices by colors, 2 and in (a), (b) and (c) or an extra vertex of degree 5 in (d) forces a coloring of the 6-cycle by a sequence (, 2,,, 2, ) in cyclic order. References [] V. A. Aksenov. On continuation of -colouring of planar graphs. Diskret. Anal. Novosibirsk, 26: 9, 974. in Russian. [2] V. A. Aksenov. Chromatic connected vertices in planar graphs. Diskret. Analiz, :5 6, 977. in Russian. [] V. A. Aksenov, O. V. Borodin, and N. A. Glebov. On the continuation of a -coloring from two vertices in a plane graph without -cycles. Diskretn. Anal. Issled. Oper. Ser., 9: 6, 2002. in Russian. [4] O. V. Borodin. A new proof of Grünbaum s color theorem. Discrete Math., 69:77 8, 997. [5] O. V. Borodin. Colorings of plane graphs: a survey. Discrete Math., accepted, DOI:0.06/j.disc.202..0, 202. [6] O. V. Borodin, A. N. Glebov, and A. Raspaud. Planar graphs without triangles adjacent to cycles of length from 4 to 7 are -colorable. Thomassen s special issue of Discrete Math., 0:2584 2594, 200. [7] O. V. Borodin, M. Montassier, and A. Raspaud. Planar graphs without adjacent cycles of length at most seven are -colorable. Discrete Math., 0:67 7, 200.

[8] O.V. Borodin, A.N. Glebov, M. Montassier, and A. Raspaud. Planar graphs without 5- and 7-cycles and without adjacent triangles are - colorable. Journal of Combinatorial Theory, Series B, 99:668 67, 2009. [9] O.V. Borodin, A.N. Glebov, A. Raspaud, and M.R. Salavatipour. Planar graphs without cycles of length from 4 to 7 are -colorable. Journal of Combinatorial Theory, Series B, 9:0, 2005. [0] M. Chen, A. Raspaud, and W. Wang. Three-coloring planar graphs without short cycles. Inform. Process. Lett., 0:4 8, 2007. [] M. Chen and W. Wang. On -colorable planar graphs without short cycles. Appl. Math. Lett., 2:96 965, 2008. [2] G. A. Dirac. A theorem of R. L. Brooks and a conjecture of H. Hadwiger. Proc. London Math., 7:6 95, 957. [] Z. Dvořák, D. Král, and R. Thomas. Coloring planar graphs with triangles far apart. submitted, 2009. [4] H. Grötzsch. Ein Dreifarbenzatz für Dreikreisfreie Netze auf der Kugel. Math.-Natur. Reihe, 8:09 20, 959. [5] B. Grünbaum. Grötzsch s theorem on -coloring. Michigan Math. J., 0:0 0, 96. [6] I. Havel. On a conjecture of Grünbaum. Journal of Combinatorial Theory, Series B, 7:84 86, 969. [7] T. Jensen and C. Thomassen. The color space of a graph. J. Graph Theory, 4:24 245, 2000. [8] T. R. Jensen and B. Toft. Graph Coloring Problems. Wiley-Interscience Series in Discrete Mathematics and Optimization, John Wiley & Sons, New York, 995. [9] A. V. Kostochka and M. Yancey. Ore s Conjecture for k = 4 and Grötzsch theorem. Submitted, 202. [20] A. V. Kostochka and M. Yancey. Ore s Conjecture is almost true. Submitted, 202. 2

[2] X. Luo, M. Chen, and W. F. Wang. On -colorable planar graphs without cycles of four lengths. Inform. Process. Lett., 0:50 56, 2007. [22] O. Ore. The Four Color Problem. Academic Press, New York, 967. [2] R. Steinberg. The state of the three color problem. Quo Vadis, Graph Theory? Ann. Discrete Math., 55:2 248, 99. [24] R. Thomas and B. Walls. Three-coloring Klein bottle graphs of girth five. J. Combin. Theory Ser. B, 92:5 5, 2004. [25] C. Thomassen. Grötzsch s -color theorem and its counterparts for the torus and the projective plane. Journal of Combinatorial Theory Series B, 62:268 279, 994. [26] W. Wang and M. Chen. On -colorable planar graphs without prescribed cycles. Discrete Math., 07:2820 2825, 2007. [27] W. Wang and M. Chen. Planar graphs without 4,6,8-cycles are - colorable. Sci. China A, 50:552 562, 2007. [28] Y.Q. Wang, X.H. Mao, H.J. Lu, and W.F. Wang. On -colorability of planar graphs without adjacent short cycles. Sci. China Math., 5:29 2, 200. [29] B. Xu. On -colorable plane graphs without 5- and 7-cycles. Journal of Combinatorial Theory, Series B, 96:958 96, 2006. [0] D. A. Youngs. 4-chromatic projective graphs. J. Graph Theory, 2:29 227, 996.