SOME PROPERTIES OF WEAK DOMINATION IN AN EXCHANGE MARKET WITH INDIVISIBLE GOODS*

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "SOME PROPERTIES OF WEAK DOMINATION IN AN EXCHANGE MARKET WITH INDIVISIBLE GOODS*"

Transcription

1 Vol. 42, No. 4, December 1991 SOME PROPERTIES OF WEAK DOMINATION IN AN EXCHANGE MARKET WITH INDIVISIBLE GOODS* By JUN WAKO We investigate general properties of weak domination in the Shapley-Scarf exchange model with indivisible goods. We prove that every weakly dominated allocation is weakly dominated by some competitive allocation. Furthermore, if an allocation does not weakly dominate some other allocation, it is a weakly dominated allocation or the two allocations are indifferent. By using these results, we show that every non-competitive allocation is weakly dominated by some competitive allocation. The nonempty strong core proves to be a von Neumann-Morgenstern solution. We give also a necessary and sufficient condition for the equivalence of the strong core and the competitive allocations. 1. Introduction This paper studies some general properties of weak domination in an exchange model with indivisible goods. We consider the model of Shapley and Scarf (1974). In this model, each trader owns one indivisible good and wants to exchange it for one preferable indivisible good. Every trader has no use for more than one unit of indivisible goods. A typical example in the literature is a trade of houses.1) We could also consider an exchange of tasks assigned to agents in this framework. Shapley and Scarf showed that even in such a discrete model a competitive equilibrium always exists. This paper, following Roth and Postlewaite (1977) and Wako (1984), further investigates how a competitive allocation relates to other allocations through weak domi nation,and generalizes some previous results. Given two allocations in an exchange market, we say that one allocation weakly dominates the other through a coalition of traders if some member of the coalition is better off in the former than in the latter while the other members are not worse off in the former, and the coalition can attain the same consumption as in the former allocation by redistributing their initial resources among themselves. An allocation weakly dominates some other allocation if there is such a coa lition. The set of allocations that are not weakly dominated by any allocation is called the strong core. * This research is supported by the grant of Tokyo Center of Economic Researcḥ The author wishes to thank Professors Ahmet Alkan, Jerzy Legut, Shigeo Muto, Koh Nishihara, Marilda Sotomayor, Walter Trockel and Myrna Wooders for their helpful comments and encouragement. 1) Quinzii (1984) and Wako (1991) considered an extended Shapley-Scarf model with money

2 The gcore h in Debreu and Scarf (1963) is in fact the strong core. In their standard exchange mar ketwith perfectly divisible goods, the strong core exists and contains the competitive allocations. However, Shapley and Scarf (1974) pointed out that the strong core does not necessarily exist in their indivisible good market with non-convex and satiable preferences. In the Shapley-Scarf model, the strong core may be empty, while a competitive equilibrium exists. Roth and Postlewaite (1977) then proved that if no trader is indifferent between any goods, the strong core exists and consists of a unique competitive allocation, which weakly domi natesany other allocation. In general, Wako (1984) showed that the strong core is a subset, and may be a nonempty proper subset of the competitive allocations. These results are not obtained in a standard exchange model with perfectly divisible goods. Some basic feature should be found out in the weak domination relation in the Shapley-Scarf model. We investigate this question. In the following section, we define the details of the Shapley-Scarf model, the weak domination relation and its related solution concepts. In Section 3, we introduce the competitive equilib riuminto the model and review the previous results. The main results are stated in Section 4. In the Shapley-Scarf model, every weakly dominated allocation is weakly dominated by some competitive allocation. If an allocation does not weakly dominate some other alocation, it is a weakly dominated allocation or the two allocations are equivalent in preference. These proper tiesgeneralize some previous results. Every non-competitive allocation is weakly dominated by some competitive allocation. The nonempty strong core is a von Neumann-Morgenstern solu tion.furthermore, the strong core coincides with the set of competitive allocations if and only if any two competitive allocations are equivalent in preference. Proofs are given in Section The Shapley-Scarf Model and the Concept of Weak Domination We consider the Shapley-Scarf model (1974). This model has n traders, each with one indivis iblegood initially. Each trader wants only one preferable indivisible good in exchange for his good, whereas there is no medium of exchange. Let N={1,...,n} be the set of traders. We denote trader is initial endowment by the i-th unit vector ei in Rn, namely, trader i owns one unit of the i-th indivisible good. Since each trader wants only one indivisible good, the consumption set is the set G(N)={e1,...,en}. Trader i has a preference Ri on G(N). The expression ekrieh means that trader i weakly prefers the k-th good to the h-th good. We denote ekpieh if he prefers the k-th good to the h-th good, and ekiieh if he is indifferent between the two goods. An allocation is defined as a bijection from N onto G(N). A nonempty subset S of N is called a coalition S. We extend the definition of G(N) to any coalition S, namely, let G(S)={ek k S}. The set G(S) shows the goods that coalition S can redistribute among themselves. For a given allocation x, we define a trading cycle in x to be any coalition S such that x(s)=g(s) and x(s') G(S') for any nonempty S' ¼S with S' S, where x(s)= {x(i) i S} and x(s') is defined similarly. If S={i1,...,it} is a trading cycle in x, we have, by reindexing if necessary, x(ik)+eik+1 for k=1,...,t-1 and x(it)=ei1. A trading cycle S in x is a minimal effective coalition under x in the sense that the members of S can obtain the goods assigned in x by themselves

3 J. Wako: Some Properties of Weak Domination in an Exchange Market It is defined that an allocation x weakly dominates an allocation y (through S) if and only if there exists a trading cycle S in x such that x(i)riy(i) for each i S, and x(j)pjy(j) for some j S. The strong core is the set of allocations that are not weakly dominated by any allocation. Any nonempty set K of allocations is defined to be a von Neumann-Morgenstern solution defined by weak domination if and only if 1) no allocation in K is weakly dominated by any allocation in K, and 2) any allocation that is not in K is weakly dominated by some allocation in K. The con ditions1) and 2) are called internal stability and external stability, respectively. In the following, we simply write ga von Neumann-Morgenstern solution. h 3. Competitive Equilibrium and Previous Results on Its Properties Let p=(p1,...,pn) be a vector of positive numbers and let each pi denote a price of the i-th good. A competitive equilibrium of our model is defined as a pair <x, p> of an allocation x and a price vector p satisfying (3.1) p x(i) p ei for each i N, and (3.2) for each i N, x(i)rieh for any eh G(N) with p eh p ei. Condition (3.1) is a budget constraint. (3.2) is a requirement for utility maximization within a budget. An allocation x is said to be competitive if there is a price vector p with the pair <x, p> being a competitive equilibrium. Let R be any nonempty subset of N. For trader i R, define B(R, i)={ek G(R) ekrieh for any eh G(R)}. This set shows the goods that trader i likes best among those avail ablein R. A top trading cycle for R is defined to be any coalition T ¼R for which there is a bijection xt from T onto G(T) with (3.3) xt(i) B(R, i) for each i T, and (3.4) xt(t') G(T') for any nonempty T' ¼T with T' T. There exists at least one top trading cycle for any R. In fact, starting with any trader in R, repeat the procedure: as a next trader, choose anyone among the owners of the goods that the trader chosen immediately before likes best in G(R). Since R is a finite set, we must get a cycle, namely, a top trading cycle for R. The method of top trading cycles2) is the procedure that constructs an allocation by using top trading cycles. In this procedure, we first find any sequence of disjoint top trading cycles {T1,...,Tt} such that (3.5) N= ¾tk=1Tk and Tk is a top trading cycle for N _ ¾k-1h=1Th for k=1,...,t, where N _ ¾k-1h=1Th=N for k=1. To do this, take any top trading cycle for N as T1; take any top trading cycle for N _T1 as T2; proceed in the same manner until there is no remainders. Since N is a finite set, we get a required sequence and also a bijection xtk with (3.3) and (3.4) for each Tk. Then define an allocation x by putting x(i)=xtk(i) for each i in each Tk {T1,...,Tt}. 2) This procedure is due to Professor David Gale

4 Theorem A (Shapley and Scarf 1974). In the Shapley-Scarf model, there is at least one com petitiveallocation, and the set of competitive allocations coincides with the set of allocations obtainable by the method of top trading cycles. Let x be any allocation obtained by the method of top trading cycles, and {T1,...,Tt} be the associated sequence of top trading cycles. Take any numbers Ĕ1, Ĕ2,...,Ĕt with Ĕ1> Ĕ 2> c>Ĕt>0. Then from (3.5), x proves to be competitive under prices p=(p1,...,pn) with pi=Ĕk for each i in each Tk {T1,...,Tt}. Thus any allocation obtained by the method above is competitive. This also shows the existence. Conversely, let x be any competitive allocation and p=(p1,...,pn) be its competitive prices. Let T1,...,Tt be all the trading cycles in x. Then for each Tk, there must be a constant Ĕk with pi=Ĕk for each i Tk. Arrange the trading cycles in such an order that Tk1, Tk2,...,Tkt andĔ k1 Ĕk2 c Ĕkt. Since x is competitive, this sequence is that of top trading cycles satisfy ing(3.5). Thus we can obtain any competitive allocation by the method of top trading cycles. From Theorem A, if no trader is indifferent between any goods, there is a unique competitive allocation, since we get a unique allocation by the method of top trading cycles under this assumption of strict preferences. Assuming strict preferences, Roth and Postlewaite (1977) showed external stability of a unique competitive allocation and its equivalence to the strong core. Wako (1984) proved the general inclusion relationship between the competitive allocations and the strong core. These results show distinctive properties of the Shapley-Scarf model. Theorem B (Both and Postlewaite 1977). If no trader is indifferent between any goods, then a unique competitive allocation weakly dominates any other allocation. Theorem C (Roth and Postlewaite 1977). If no trader is indifferent between any goods, then the strong core is nonempty, and contains exactly one allocation, which is the unique competitive allocation. Theorem D (Wako 1984). The strong core is included in the set of competitive allocations. 4. Weak Domination by Competitive Allocations In the Shapley-Scarf model, the competitive equilibrium has close relation to the concept of weak domination. By investigating an underlying property of the weak domination relation, we could tell the feature of the Shapley-Scarf model more lucidly. Then we generally investi gatehow given allocations are related to a competitive allocation through weak domination. As basic results, we can prove the following propositions for the case that an allocation x weakly dominates an allocation y, and the other case that an allocation x does not weakly dominate an allocation y. Proposition 1. If an allocation x weakly dominates an allocation y, then y is weakly dominated by some competitive allocation z

5 J. Wako: Some Properties of Weak Domination in an Exchange Market Proposition 2. If an allocation x does not weakly dominate an allocation y, then (1) x(i)iiy(i) for any i N, or (2) x is weakly dominated by some allocation z. Proposition 1 means that every weakly dominated allocation is weakly dominated by some competitive allocation. Let us say that allocations x and y are equivalent in preference if x(i)iiy(i) for any i N. Proposition 2, together with Proposition 1, means that if an allocation does not weakly dominate some other allocation and if they are not equivalent in preference, the former is weakly dominated by some competitive allocation. Note that Proposition 2 is not trivial, since the fact that allocation x does not weakly dominate allocation y does not imply that x is weakly dominated by y. Using these propositions and Theorems A and D, we can generalize Theorems B and C for the case that a trader may be indifferent between some goods. Firstly, Proposition 1 generally proves external stability of the set of competitive allocations, since Theorem D implies that every non - competitive allocation is a weakly dominated allocation. Theorem 1. Every non-competitive allocation is weakly dominated by some competitive allo cation.3) The set of competitive allocations is stable externally, and not necessarily stable internally. Since we allow indifferences in traders' preferences, the set of competitive allocations does not necessarily coincide with the strong core. In the case of non-equivalence, some competitive allo cationis weakly dominated by another competitive allocation (Theorem D and Proposition 1). The strong core has internal stability by its definition. Furthermore, Proposition 2 proves its external stability. Theorem 2. (1) Any strong core allocation weakly dominates all the other allocations that are not contained in the strong core; (2) Any two strong core allocations are equivalent in preference. Note that when the strong core is empty, the statements hold in the trivial sense. Result (1) shows external stability of the strong core. Thus when the strong core is nonempty, it is a unique4) von Neumann-Morgenstern solution. Note that external stability here holds in a strong sense that any allocation outside the strong core is weakly dominated by every strong core allo cation.furthermore, by result (2), the nonempty strong core gives a unique point in terms of preference. The strong core has the remarkable properties as above. We can guarantee its existence when 3) Shapley and Scarf (1974, p. 32) raised a question: Can there be a non-competitive allocation that is not weakly dominated by a competitive allocation? Theorem 1 gives a negative answer to this question. (See also Roth and Postlewaite, 1977, p. 136.) 4) If the strong core is a von Neumann-Morgenstern solution, there is no other set of allocations with internal and external stability

6 it coincides with the set of competitive allocations. In addition, the equivalence of the two sets is necessary for internal stability of the set of competitive allocations. From our results, we can tell in what situation the equivalence holds. A necessary condition derives from Theorem 2-(2), and it proves to be sufficient by Proposition 1 and Theorem D. Theorem 3. The strong core coincides with the set of competitive allocations Wand only if any two competitive allocations are equivalent in preference. It is not yet known how the condition above can be completely represented by preference profiles. However, we can prove Theorem C as a special case of our result. Theorem 3 implies that if a unique competitive allocation exists, the strong core is a singleton containing the com petitiveallocation. Theorem C derives from this fact, since under the assumption of Theorem C we have a unique competitive allocation by Theorem A. Note that Theorem 3 gives also a necessary and sufficient condition for the set of competitive allocation to become a von Neumann-Morgenstern solution. However, when the condition is violated, a von Neumann-Morgenstern solution may contain a non-competitive allocation (see Example 1). The general existence of a von Neumann-Morgenstern tion. Finally, we show how our results work by examples. solution is an open ques Example 1.5) Let N={1, 2, 3} and the preferences of the traders be as follows: (1) e2p1e3i1e1 (2) e1i2e3p2e2 (3) e2p3e1p3e3 Let x=(h, i, j) denote an allocation x with x(1)=eh, x(2)=ei, and x(3)=ej. By the method of top trading cycles, we can find two competitive allocations x=(1, 3, 2) and x=(2, 1, 3). Since these allocations weakly dominate each other, the strong core is empty by Theorem D. Allocations y=(2, 3, 1) and y=(3, 1, 2) do not weakly dominate each other, and are not equivalent in preference. Thus by Propositions 1 and 2, they must be weakly dominated by some competitive allocations. In fact, y and y are weakly dominated by competitive alloca tionsx and x, respectively. Further, x is weakly dominated by y through N. The remaining allocations z=(1, 2, 3) and z=(3, 2, 1) are weakly dominated by the other four allocations. As Theorem 1 shows, the set of competitive allocations has external stability. However, it does not have internal stability, nor does it coincide with the strong core. According to Theorem 3, these phenomena arise from the fact that the two competitive allocations are not equivalent in preference. Although the strong core is empty in this example, the set {x, y} is the unique von Neumann-Morgenstern solution. Example 2. Let N={1, 2, 3} and the preferences of the traders be as follows: 5) This example is due to Koh Nishihara

7 (1) e3i1e2p1e1 J. Wako: Some Properties of Weak Domination an Exchange Market (2) e1i2e3p2e2 (3) e2i3e1p3e3 In this example, all the allocations except z=(1, 2, 3) are competitive. Since x=(1, 3, 2) and x=(2, 1, 3), for example, are not equivalent in preference, the strong core does not coincide with the set of competitive allocations. The strong core of this example is the set of allocations y=(2, 3, 1) and y=(3, 1, 2). As Theorem 2 shows, both y and y weakly dominate the other allocations except them, and y and y are equivalent in preference. This nonempty strong core is the unique von Neumann-Morgenstern solution. Remark. Wako (1990) considered what sort of competitive allocation a strong core allocation is. It was proved that allocation x is a strong core allocation if and only if x is a competitive allocation for which there exists a price vector with conditions (3.1), (3.2) and for each i N, x(i)pieh for any eh G(N) with P Eeh<p Eei. Theorem 2-(1) was proved in that paper by using this fact. 5. Proofs of Propositions and Theorems We will prove Propositions 1 and 2, and Theorems 2 and 3. Theorem 1 follows from Proposi tion1 and Theorem D immediately Proof of Proposition 1 Suppose that an allocation x weakly dominates an allocation y. If x is competitive, the proposi tionis clear. Thus we assume that x is not competitive. Since x weakly dominates y, there exists a trading cycle S* in x with x(i)riy(i) for all i S*, and x(j)pjy(j) for some j S*. We will make top trading cycles from allocations x, y, and trading cycle S*, and then show that those cycles give a competitive allocation which weakly dominates y. For any given nonempty subset R of N, a nonempty subset T of R is called a top trading cycle for R under (x, y, S*) if and only if there exists a bijection zt from T onto G(T) satisfying (5.1) zt(i) B(R, i) for each i T, (5.2) zt(i)=y(i) if i T _S* and y(i) B(R, i), (5.3) zt(i)=x(i) if i T S* and x(i) B(R, i), and (5.4) zt(t') G (T') for any nonempty proper subset T' of T. A top trading cycle for R under (x, y, S*) is a top trading cycle for R satisfying the conditional requirements (5.2) and (5.3). Since N is a finite set, for any nonempty subset R ¼N, we can find at least one top trading cycle for R under (x, y, S*). Then let {T1,...,Tt} be a partition of N such that (5.5) Tk is a top trading cycle for N _ ¾k-1k=1Th under (x, y, S*) for k=1,...,t, where N _ ¾k-1k=1Th=N for k=1. Let ztk be the bijection associated with top trading cycle Tk under (x, y, S*) for each k=1,...,t. Then define the allocation z by (5.6) z(i)=ztk(i) for each i Tk and k=1,...,t

8 Since T1,...,Tt satisfy condition (5.5), z is a competitive allocation. We will show that the competitive allocation z weakly dominates allocation y. At first, we will prove the following claim: Claim 1. Let k be a number with 1 k t. If z(i)=y(i) for each i ¾kh=1Th, then Th S* =_??_ for each Th {T1,...,Tk}. From Claim 1, it is impossible that z(i)=y(i) for all i N= ¾th=1Th, since _??_ S* ¼N. Thus there exists a Tk {T1,...,Tt} with z(j) y(j) for some j Tk. Then we will prove Claim 2: Claim 2. Let Tk* {T1,...,Tt} be the trading cycle whose index is minimum among those cycles Th {T1,...,Tt} with z(j) y(j) for some j Th. Then allocation z weakly domi natesallocation y through Tk*. Since allocation z is competitive, Proposition 1 is shown if we prove these claims. (Proof of Claim 1) Assume that Claim 1 does not hold, namely, (5.7) { z(i)=y(i) for each i ¾kh=1Th, and Th S* _??_ for some Th {T1,...,Tk}. Let Tm be the trading cycle with the minimum index among those Th {T1,...,Tk} with Th S* _??_. For a general description of a proof, we prove the case of m>1. The claim can be proved in the same manner for m=1. By the definition of Tm, we have S* ¼N _ ¾m-1h=1Th. Since S* is a trading cycle in x, we have x(j) G(N _ ¾m-1h=1Th) for each j S*. Since we have assumed that z(i)=y(i) for each i Tm, it must hold that y(i) B(N _ ¾m-1h=1Th, i) for each i Tm by (5.1), (5.5) and (5.6). However, x(j)rjy(j) for each j Tm S*. Thus by (5.3), we must have (5.8) z(j)=x(j)=y(j) for each j Tm S*. The first equality of (5.8) means z(tm S*)=x(Tm S*) ¼G(Tm S*), since z(tm)=g(tm) and x(s*)=g(s*). Then the fact that z is a bijection from N onto G(N) implies (5.9) z(tm S*)=x(Tm S*)=G(Tm S*). Since Tm and S* are trading cycles in z and x, respectively, we have z(t') G(T') for any nonempty proper subset T' of Tm, and x(s') G(S') for any nonempty proper subset S' of S*. Since Tm S* _??_, equation (5.9) holds only if (5.10) Tm=S*. Thus it follows from (5.8) that x(i)=y(i) for each i S*. However, this is impossible, since allocation x weakly dominates y through S*. This contradiction is due to assumption (5.7). Hence Claim 1 holds. (Proof of Claim 2) For a general description of a proof, we prove the case of k*>1. The claim -310-

9 J. Wako: Some Properties of Weak Domination in an Exchange Market can be proved in the same manner for k*=1. From the definition of Tk*, (5.11) z(i)=y(i) for each i Th with 1 h<k*. Thus T1,...,Tk*-1 are also trading cycles in y, and so y(i) G(N _ ¾k*-1h=1Th) for each i Tk*. Since Tk* is a top trading cycle for N _ ¾k*-1h=1Th, (5.12) z(i)riy(i) for each i Tk*. Regarding Tk* and S*, we have the following three possible cases: (case 1) Tk* S*=_??_, (case 2) Tk* S* _??_ and z(j) x(j) for some j Tk* S*, or (case 3) Tk* S* _??_ and z(j)=x(j) for all j Tk* S*. Then we will prove Claim 2 for each case. (case 1) By the definition of Tk*, there exists a j Tk* with z(j) y(j). Since Tk* S* =_??_, if y(j) B(N _ ¾k*-1h=1Th,j), we must have z(j)=y(j) by (5.2), (5.5) and (5.6). Thus y(j)_??_b(n _ ¾k*-1h=1Th,j) for j Tk* with z(j) y(j). Since y(j) G(N _ ¾k*-1h=1 Th) and z(j) B(N _ ¾k*-1h=1Th,j), z(j)pjy(j) for j Tk* with z(j) y(j). This together with (5.12) imply that z weakly dominates y through Tk*. (case 2) It follows from Claim 1 and (5.11) that S* ¼N _ ¾k*-1h=1Th. Since S* is a trading cycle in x, we have x(j) G(N _ ¾k*-1h=1Th) for each j Tk* S*. Since x(j)rjy(j) for each j S* and since Tk* is a top trading cycle for N _ ¾k*-1h=1Th under (x, y, S*), we have z(j)pjx(j)rjy(j) for j Tk* S* with z(j) x(j) by (5.3). This together with (5.12) imply that z weakly dominates y through Tk*. (case 3) If z(j)=x(j) for each j Tk* S*, we have Tk*=S* by the same argument given to show (5.10). This immediately means that z weakly dominates y through Tk*, since x weakly dominates y through S*. Claim 2 holds for every case. The proof of Proposition 1 is complete Proof of Proposition 2 Proposition 2 is equivalent to Propostion 2' below, which we will prove. Proposition 2'. If x and y are allocations satisfying i) not x(i)iiy(i) for some i N, and ii) x does not weakly dominate y, then there exists an allocation z that weakly dominates x. Let x and y be any allocations such that i) not x(i)iiy(i) for some i N, and ii) x does not weakly dominate y. By using these allocations, we partition N into the three sets X, Y and E defined by X={i N x(i)piy(i)}, Y={i N y(i)pix(i)}, E={i N x(i)iiy(i)}. By condition i), X ¾Y _??_. If Y=_??_, x weakly dominates y, since N=E ¾X and X _??_ in this case. This contradicts condition ii). Thus the set Y is nonempty

10 Define the mapping z0 from N to G(N) as follows. z0(i)={ y(i) for i N with T(i x) ¼E or i Y, x(i) for i N with T(i x)_??_ and i_??_y, where T(i x) denotes the trading cycle in x in which i is contained. T(i x) is determined uniquely. Note that mapping z0 is not necessarily a bijection from N onto G(N), and that z0(i)rix(i) for each i N. Since z0(n) ¼G(N) and N is a finite set, there exists a nonempty subset S of N with z0(s)=g(s) and z0(s') G(S') for any nonempty proper subset S' of S. We call such a set S a cycle in z0, and denote by J the set of all cycles in z0. Proposition 2' is then proved by showing the following claims: Claim 1. If there exists a cycle S J with S Y _??_, then there exists an allocation z that weakly dominates x. Claim 2. The exists a cycle S J with S Y _??_. (Proof of Claim 1) Let S be a cycle in z0 with S Y _??_. We have z0(i)rix(i) for each i S, z0(j)=y(j) and z0(j)pjx(j) for each j S Y, and z0(s)=g(s). Then define the mapping z from N onto G(N) by z(i)={ z0(i) for i S ei for i N _S. This mapping z is an allocation that weakly dominates x through S. (Proof of Claim 2) At first, we will show that (5.13) T(i* x)_??_e for some i* ¾S JS. To prove this, assume on the contrary that (5.14) T(i x) ¼E for each i ¾S JS. This implies ¾S JS ¼E, because i T(i x) for any i N. Since Y E=_??_, we have Y ¼N _ ¾S JS. Since Y is nonempty, the set N _ ¾S JS is nonempty. Here, if z0(i) G(N _ ¾S JS) for any i N _ ¾S JS, there must be a cycle S' in z0 with S' ¼N _ ¾S JS. However, this is impossible since S' must be contained in J. Thus there exist some j* N _ ¾S JS and S* J with z0(j*) G(S*). From assumption (5.14), we have T(i x) ¼E for any i S*. By the definition of z0, z0(i)=y(i) for each i S*, and so y(s*)=g(s*). Since y is a bijection from N onto G(N), we must have z0(j*) y(j*). Again by the definition of z0, z0(j*)=x(j*) and T(j* x)_??_e. Here, let i* be the element or N with x(j*)=ei*. Then we have T(i* x)_??_e and i* S*EJ, since T(i* x)=t(j* x)_??_e and x(j*)=z0(j*)=ei* G(S*). However, this contra dictsassumption (5.14). Thus claim (5.13) holds

11 J. Wako: Some Properties of Weak Domination in an Exchange Market Now we will prove Claim 2. Assume that it does not hold, i.e., (5.15) S Y=_??_ for any S J. From claim (5.13), there is a cycle S* J with T(i x)_??_e for some i S*. We may sup posethat S*={i1,...,it} and T(i1 x)_??_e, z0(it)=ei1, and z0(ik)=eik+1 for k=1,...,t-1. It follows from assumption (5.15) that ik_??_y for each ik S*. Since T(i1 x)_??_e, we have z0(i1)=x(i1)=ei2 by the definition of z0. Equation x(i1)=ei2 implies T(i1 x)=t(i2 x), and so T(i2 x)_??_e. Thus we have z0(i2)=x(i2)=ei3. Repeating the same argument, we have z0(i)=x(i) for each i S*. This means that S* is a trading cycle in x, since S* is a cycle in z0. Thus S*=T(i1 x), and sos *_??_E. Further, since S* Y=_??_ by (5.15), we have S* ¼E ¾X and S* X _??_. This means that x weakly dominates y through S*. However, this contradicts condition ii). Thus Claim 2 holds. The proof of Proposition 2 is complete Proof of Theorem 2 To see (1), assume that a strong core allocation x does not weakly dominate an allocationy out sidethe strong core. Since x and y are not equivalent in preference, x must be a weakly dominated allocation by Proposition 2. However, this contradicts that x is in the strong core. To see (2), assume that there are two strong core allocations x and y that are not equivalent in preference. Since x cannot weakly dominate y, x must be a weakly dominated allocation by Pro position2. This contradicts that x is in the strong core. Hence Theorem 2 holds Proof of Theorem 3 (Necessity) Suppose that the strong core coincides with the set of competitive allocations. Then any competitive allocation is also a strong core allocation. Thus by Theorem 2-(2), any two competitive allocations are equivalent in preference. (Sufficiency) Suppose that any two competitive allocations are equivalent in preference. Here, assume that there is a competitive allocation x that is not contained in the strong core. By Proposition 1, x must be weakly dominated by some competitive allocation z. However, this is impossible, since any two competitive allocations are assumed to be equivalent in preference. Thus any competitive allocation is contained in the strong core. Since the strong core is a subset of the competitive allocations by Theorem D, the strong core coincides with the set of com petitiveallocations. (K omazawa University) REFERENCES Debreu, G. and H. Scarf (1963) ga Limit Theorem on the Core of an Economy, h International Economic Review, Vol. 4, pp Quinzii, M. (1984) gcore and Competitive Equilibria with Indivisibilities, h International Journal of Game Theory, Vol. 13, pp Roth, A. E. and A. Postlewaite (1977) gweak versus Strong Domination in a Market with Indivisible Goods, h Journal of Mathematical Economics, Vol. 4, pp

12 Shapley, L. and H. Scarf (1974) gon Cores and Indivisibility, h Journal of Mathematical Economics, Vol. 1, pp Wako, J. (1984) ga Note on the Strong Core of a Market with Indivisible Goods, h Journal of Mathematical Economics, Vol. 13, pp (1990) gstrong Core and Competitive Allocations of the Shapley-Scarf Exchange Market with Indivisible Goods, h Komadai Keiei Kenkyu, Vol. 21, No. 4, pp (in Japanese). - (1991) gstrong Core and Competitive Equilibria of an Exchange Market with Indivisible Goods, h forthcoming in International Economic Review

Dynamics, stability, and foresight in the Shapley-Scarf housing market. Discussion Paper No

Dynamics, stability, and foresight in the Shapley-Scarf housing market. Discussion Paper No Dynamics, stability, and foresight in the Shapley-Scarf housing market Yoshio Kamijo Ryo Kawasaki Discussion Paper No. 2008-12 October 2008 Dynamics, stability, and foresight in the Shapley-Scarf housing

More information

Edge Colorings of Complete Multipartite Graphs Forbidding Rainbow Cycles

Edge Colorings of Complete Multipartite Graphs Forbidding Rainbow Cycles Theory and Applications of Graphs Volume 4 Issue 2 Article 2 November 2017 Edge Colorings of Complete Multipartite Graphs Forbidding Rainbow Cycles Peter Johnson johnspd@auburn.edu Andrew Owens Auburn

More information

Basic Graph Theory with Applications to Economics

Basic Graph Theory with Applications to Economics Basic Graph Theory with Applications to Economics Debasis Mishra February 6, What is a Graph? Let N = {,..., n} be a finite set. Let E be a collection of ordered or unordered pairs of distinct elements

More information

Winning Positions in Simplicial Nim

Winning Positions in Simplicial Nim Winning Positions in Simplicial Nim David Horrocks Department of Mathematics and Statistics University of Prince Edward Island Charlottetown, Prince Edward Island, Canada, C1A 4P3 dhorrocks@upei.ca Submitted:

More information

Network Topology and Equilibrium Existence in Weighted Network Congestion Games

Network Topology and Equilibrium Existence in Weighted Network Congestion Games Network Topology and Equilibrium Existence in Weighted Network Congestion Games Igal Milchtaich, Bar-Ilan University August 2010 Abstract. Every finite noncooperative game can be presented as a weighted

More information

Basic Graph Theory with Applications to Economics

Basic Graph Theory with Applications to Economics Basic Graph Theory with Applications to Economics Debasis Mishra February, 0 What is a Graph? Let N = {,..., n} be a finite set. Let E be a collection of ordered or unordered pairs of distinct elements

More information

9.5 Equivalence Relations

9.5 Equivalence Relations 9.5 Equivalence Relations You know from your early study of fractions that each fraction has many equivalent forms. For example, 2, 2 4, 3 6, 2, 3 6, 5 30,... are all different ways to represent the same

More information

Core Membership Computation for Succinct Representations of Coalitional Games

Core Membership Computation for Succinct Representations of Coalitional Games Core Membership Computation for Succinct Representations of Coalitional Games Xi Alice Gao May 11, 2009 Abstract In this paper, I compare and contrast two formal results on the computational complexity

More information

Adjacent: Two distinct vertices u, v are adjacent if there is an edge with ends u, v. In this case we let uv denote such an edge.

Adjacent: Two distinct vertices u, v are adjacent if there is an edge with ends u, v. In this case we let uv denote such an edge. 1 Graph Basics What is a graph? Graph: a graph G consists of a set of vertices, denoted V (G), a set of edges, denoted E(G), and a relation called incidence so that each edge is incident with either one

More information

ON THE EMPTY CONVEX PARTITION OF A FINITE SET IN THE PLANE**

ON THE EMPTY CONVEX PARTITION OF A FINITE SET IN THE PLANE** Chin. Ann. of Math. 23B:(2002),87-9. ON THE EMPTY CONVEX PARTITION OF A FINITE SET IN THE PLANE** XU Changqing* DING Ren* Abstract The authors discuss the partition of a finite set of points in the plane

More information

Symmetric Product Graphs

Symmetric Product Graphs Rochester Institute of Technology RIT Scholar Works Theses Thesis/Dissertation Collections 5-20-2015 Symmetric Product Graphs Evan Witz Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarworks.rit.edu/theses

More information

Representation of Finite Games as Network Congestion Games

Representation of Finite Games as Network Congestion Games Representation of Finite Games as Network Congestion Games Igal Milchtaich To cite this version: Igal Milchtaich. Representation of Finite Games as Network Congestion Games. Roberto Cominetti and Sylvain

More information

The College Admissions Problem Reconsidered

The College Admissions Problem Reconsidered The College Admissions Problem Reconsidered Zhenhua Jiao School of Economics Shanghai University of Finance and Economics Shanghai, 200433, China Guoqiang Tian Department of Economics Texas A&M University

More information

Efficient Random Assignment with Constrained Rankings

Efficient Random Assignment with Constrained Rankings Efficient Random Assignment with Constrained Rankings Gabriel Carroll Department of Economics, Massachusetts Institute of Technology E52-391, 50 Memorial Drive, Cambridge MA 02142, USA gdc@mit.edu January

More information

Lower bounds and recursive methods for the problem of adjudicating conflicting claims

Lower bounds and recursive methods for the problem of adjudicating conflicting claims Lower bounds and recursive methods for the problem of adjudicating conflicting claims Diego Dominguez University of Rochester March 31, 006 Abstract For the problem of adjudicating conflicting claims,

More information

Theorem 3.1 (Berge) A matching M in G is maximum if and only if there is no M- augmenting path.

Theorem 3.1 (Berge) A matching M in G is maximum if and only if there is no M- augmenting path. 3 Matchings Hall s Theorem Matching: A matching in G is a subset M E(G) so that no edge in M is a loop, and no two edges in M are incident with a common vertex. A matching M is maximal if there is no matching

More information

Convexity. 1 X i is convex. = b is a hyperplane in R n, and is denoted H(p, b) i.e.,

Convexity. 1 X i is convex. = b is a hyperplane in R n, and is denoted H(p, b) i.e., Convexity We ll assume throughout, without always saying so, that we re in the finite-dimensional Euclidean vector space R n, although sometimes, for statements that hold in any vector space, we ll say

More information

Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences. Convex Analysis and Economic Theory Winter Separation theorems

Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences. Convex Analysis and Economic Theory Winter Separation theorems Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences Ec 181 KC Border Convex Analysis and Economic Theory Winter 2018 Topic 8: Separation theorems 8.1 Hyperplanes and half spaces Recall that a hyperplane in

More information

ON SWELL COLORED COMPLETE GRAPHS

ON SWELL COLORED COMPLETE GRAPHS Acta Math. Univ. Comenianae Vol. LXIII, (1994), pp. 303 308 303 ON SWELL COLORED COMPLETE GRAPHS C. WARD and S. SZABÓ Abstract. An edge-colored graph is said to be swell-colored if each triangle contains

More information

Recognizing Interval Bigraphs by Forbidden Patterns

Recognizing Interval Bigraphs by Forbidden Patterns Recognizing Interval Bigraphs by Forbidden Patterns Arash Rafiey Simon Fraser University, Vancouver, Canada, and Indiana State University, IN, USA arashr@sfu.ca, arash.rafiey@indstate.edu Abstract Let

More information

General properties of staircase and convex dual feasible functions

General properties of staircase and convex dual feasible functions General properties of staircase and convex dual feasible functions JÜRGEN RIETZ, CLÁUDIO ALVES, J. M. VALÉRIO de CARVALHO Centro de Investigação Algoritmi da Universidade do Minho, Escola de Engenharia

More information

Two Characterizations of Hypercubes

Two Characterizations of Hypercubes Two Characterizations of Hypercubes Juhani Nieminen, Matti Peltola and Pasi Ruotsalainen Department of Mathematics, University of Oulu University of Oulu, Faculty of Technology, Mathematics Division, P.O.

More information

Module 11. Directed Graphs. Contents

Module 11. Directed Graphs. Contents Module 11 Directed Graphs Contents 11.1 Basic concepts......................... 256 Underlying graph of a digraph................ 257 Out-degrees and in-degrees.................. 258 Isomorphism..........................

More information

Matching and Factor-Critical Property in 3-Dominating-Critical Graphs

Matching and Factor-Critical Property in 3-Dominating-Critical Graphs Matching and Factor-Critical Property in 3-Dominating-Critical Graphs Tao Wang a,, Qinglin Yu a,b a Center for Combinatorics, LPMC Nankai University, Tianjin, China b Department of Mathematics and Statistics

More information

Maximal Monochromatic Geodesics in an Antipodal Coloring of Hypercube

Maximal Monochromatic Geodesics in an Antipodal Coloring of Hypercube Maximal Monochromatic Geodesics in an Antipodal Coloring of Hypercube Kavish Gandhi April 4, 2015 Abstract A geodesic in the hypercube is the shortest possible path between two vertices. Leader and Long

More information

Star Decompositions of the Complete Split Graph

Star Decompositions of the Complete Split Graph University of Dayton ecommons Honors Theses University Honors Program 4-016 Star Decompositions of the Complete Split Graph Adam C. Volk Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.udayton.edu/uhp_theses

More information

Powered by TCPDF (

Powered by TCPDF ( Powered by TCPDF (www.tcpdf.org) Title ON HICKS' COMPOSITE COMMODITY THEOREM Sub Title Author 長名, 寛明 (OSANA, Hiroaki) Publisher Keio Economic Society, Keio University Publication year 1982 Jtitle Keio

More information

CMSC Honors Discrete Mathematics

CMSC Honors Discrete Mathematics CMSC 27130 Honors Discrete Mathematics Lectures by Alexander Razborov Notes by Justin Lubin The University of Chicago, Autumn 2017 1 Contents I Number Theory 4 1 The Euclidean Algorithm 4 2 Mathematical

More information

Generell Topologi. Richard Williamson. May 6, 2013

Generell Topologi. Richard Williamson. May 6, 2013 Generell Topologi Richard Williamson May 6, 2013 1 8 Thursday 7th February 8.1 Using connectedness to distinguish between topological spaces I Proposition 8.1. Let (, O ) and (Y, O Y ) be topological spaces.

More information

Efficiency and Respecting Improvements in College Admissions

Efficiency and Respecting Improvements in College Admissions Efficiency and Respecting Improvements in College Admissions Zhenhua Jiao School of Economics Shanghai University of Finance and Economics Shanghai, 200433, China Guoqiang Tian Department of Economics

More information

1 Linear programming relaxation

1 Linear programming relaxation Cornell University, Fall 2010 CS 6820: Algorithms Lecture notes: Primal-dual min-cost bipartite matching August 27 30 1 Linear programming relaxation Recall that in the bipartite minimum-cost perfect matching

More information

Small Survey on Perfect Graphs

Small Survey on Perfect Graphs Small Survey on Perfect Graphs Michele Alberti ENS Lyon December 8, 2010 Abstract This is a small survey on the exciting world of Perfect Graphs. We will see when a graph is perfect and which are families

More information

On vertex types of graphs

On vertex types of graphs On vertex types of graphs arxiv:1705.09540v1 [math.co] 26 May 2017 Pu Qiao, Xingzhi Zhan Department of Mathematics, East China Normal University, Shanghai 200241, China Abstract The vertices of a graph

More information

Pebble Sets in Convex Polygons

Pebble Sets in Convex Polygons 2 1 Pebble Sets in Convex Polygons Kevin Iga, Randall Maddox June 15, 2005 Abstract Lukács and András posed the problem of showing the existence of a set of n 2 points in the interior of a convex n-gon

More information

THREE LECTURES ON BASIC TOPOLOGY. 1. Basic notions.

THREE LECTURES ON BASIC TOPOLOGY. 1. Basic notions. THREE LECTURES ON BASIC TOPOLOGY PHILIP FOTH 1. Basic notions. Let X be a set. To make a topological space out of X, one must specify a collection T of subsets of X, which are said to be open subsets of

More information

Discrete Applied Mathematics. A revision and extension of results on 4-regular, 4-connected, claw-free graphs

Discrete Applied Mathematics. A revision and extension of results on 4-regular, 4-connected, claw-free graphs Discrete Applied Mathematics 159 (2011) 1225 1230 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Discrete Applied Mathematics journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/dam A revision and extension of results

More information

Repairing Preference-Based Argumentation Frameworks

Repairing Preference-Based Argumentation Frameworks Repairing Preference-Based Argumentation Frameworks Leila Amgoud IRIT CNRS 118, route de Narbonne 31062, Toulouse Cedex 09 amgoud@irit.fr Srdjan Vesic IRIT CNRS 118, route de Narbonne 31062, Toulouse Cedex

More information

Progress Towards the Total Domination Game 3 4 -Conjecture

Progress Towards the Total Domination Game 3 4 -Conjecture Progress Towards the Total Domination Game 3 4 -Conjecture 1 Michael A. Henning and 2 Douglas F. Rall 1 Department of Pure and Applied Mathematics University of Johannesburg Auckland Park, 2006 South Africa

More information

Cooperative Games. Lecture 1: Introduction. Stéphane Airiau. ILLC - University of Amsterdam

Cooperative Games. Lecture 1: Introduction. Stéphane Airiau. ILLC - University of Amsterdam Cooperative Games Lecture 1: Introduction Stéphane Airiau ILLC - University of Amsterdam Stéphane Airiau (ILLC) - Cooperative Games Lecture 1: Introduction 1 Why study coalitional games? Cooperative games

More information

THE COINCIDENCE OF THE KERNEL AND NUCLEOLUS OF A CONVEX GAME: AN ALTERNATIVE PROOF

THE COINCIDENCE OF THE KERNEL AND NUCLEOLUS OF A CONVEX GAME: AN ALTERNATIVE PROOF THE COINCIDENCE OF THE KERNEL AND NUCLEOLUS OF A CONVEX GAME: AN ALTERNATIVE PROOF by J. Arín and I. Katsev 2013 Working Paper Series: IL. 67/13 Departamento de Fundamentos del Análisis Económico I Ekonomi

More information

Lecture 19 Thursday, March 29. Examples of isomorphic, and non-isomorphic graphs will be given in class.

Lecture 19 Thursday, March 29. Examples of isomorphic, and non-isomorphic graphs will be given in class. CIS 160 - Spring 2018 (instructor Val Tannen) Lecture 19 Thursday, March 29 GRAPH THEORY Graph isomorphism Definition 19.1 Two graphs G 1 = (V 1, E 1 ) and G 2 = (V 2, E 2 ) are isomorphic, write G 1 G

More information

Fundamental Properties of Graphs

Fundamental Properties of Graphs Chapter three In many real-life situations we need to know how robust a graph that represents a certain network is, how edges or vertices can be removed without completely destroying the overall connectivity,

More information

Module 7. Independent sets, coverings. and matchings. Contents

Module 7. Independent sets, coverings. and matchings. Contents Module 7 Independent sets, coverings Contents and matchings 7.1 Introduction.......................... 152 7.2 Independent sets and coverings: basic equations..... 152 7.3 Matchings in bipartite graphs................

More information

Matching Algorithms. Proof. If a bipartite graph has a perfect matching, then it is easy to see that the right hand side is a necessary condition.

Matching Algorithms. Proof. If a bipartite graph has a perfect matching, then it is easy to see that the right hand side is a necessary condition. 18.433 Combinatorial Optimization Matching Algorithms September 9,14,16 Lecturer: Santosh Vempala Given a graph G = (V, E), a matching M is a set of edges with the property that no two of the edges have

More information

The Structure of Bull-Free Perfect Graphs

The Structure of Bull-Free Perfect Graphs The Structure of Bull-Free Perfect Graphs Maria Chudnovsky and Irena Penev Columbia University, New York, NY 10027 USA May 18, 2012 Abstract The bull is a graph consisting of a triangle and two vertex-disjoint

More information

Pairwise stability and strategy-proofness for college admissions with budget constraints

Pairwise stability and strategy-proofness for college admissions with budget constraints Pairwise stability and strategy-proofness for college admissions with budget constraints Azar Abizada University of Rochester First draft: October 22, 2009 This version: January 5, 2012 Abstract We study

More information

This article was originally published in a journal published by Elsevier, and the attached copy is provided by Elsevier for the author s benefit and for the benefit of the author s institution, for non-commercial

More information

On the Relationships between Zero Forcing Numbers and Certain Graph Coverings

On the Relationships between Zero Forcing Numbers and Certain Graph Coverings On the Relationships between Zero Forcing Numbers and Certain Graph Coverings Fatemeh Alinaghipour Taklimi, Shaun Fallat 1,, Karen Meagher 2 Department of Mathematics and Statistics, University of Regina,

More information

Math 443/543 Graph Theory Notes 11: Graph minors and Kuratowski s Theorem

Math 443/543 Graph Theory Notes 11: Graph minors and Kuratowski s Theorem Math 443/543 Graph Theory Notes 11: Graph minors and Kuratowski s Theorem David Glickenstein November 26, 2008 1 Graph minors Let s revisit some de nitions. Let G = (V; E) be a graph. De nition 1 Removing

More information

EXERCISES SHORTEST PATHS: APPLICATIONS, OPTIMIZATION, VARIATIONS, AND SOLVING THE CONSTRAINED SHORTEST PATH PROBLEM. 1 Applications and Modelling

EXERCISES SHORTEST PATHS: APPLICATIONS, OPTIMIZATION, VARIATIONS, AND SOLVING THE CONSTRAINED SHORTEST PATH PROBLEM. 1 Applications and Modelling SHORTEST PATHS: APPLICATIONS, OPTIMIZATION, VARIATIONS, AND SOLVING THE CONSTRAINED SHORTEST PATH PROBLEM EXERCISES Prepared by Natashia Boland 1 and Irina Dumitrescu 2 1 Applications and Modelling 1.1

More information

Nim-Regularity of Graphs

Nim-Regularity of Graphs Nim-Regularity of Graphs Nathan Reading School of Mathematics, University of Minnesota Minneapolis, MN 55455 reading@math.umn.edu Submitted: November 24, 1998; Accepted: January 22, 1999 Abstract. Ehrenborg

More information

(Received Judy 13, 1971) (devised Nov. 12, 1971)

(Received Judy 13, 1971) (devised Nov. 12, 1971) J. Math. Vol. 25, Soc. Japan No. 1, 1973 Minimal 2-regular digraphs with given girth By Mehdi BEHZAD (Received Judy 13, 1971) (devised Nov. 12, 1971) 1. Abstract. A digraph D is r-regular if degree v =

More information

Monochromatic loose-cycle partitions in hypergraphs

Monochromatic loose-cycle partitions in hypergraphs Monochromatic loose-cycle partitions in hypergraphs András Gyárfás Alfréd Rényi Institute of Mathematics Hungarian Academy of Sciences Budapest, P.O. Box 27 Budapest, H-364, Hungary gyarfas.andras@renyi.mta.hu

More information

Introduction to Graph Theory

Introduction to Graph Theory Introduction to Graph Theory George Voutsadakis 1 1 Mathematics and Computer Science Lake Superior State University LSSU Math 351 George Voutsadakis (LSSU) Introduction to Graph Theory August 2018 1 /

More information

Lecture 15: The subspace topology, Closed sets

Lecture 15: The subspace topology, Closed sets Lecture 15: The subspace topology, Closed sets 1 The Subspace Topology Definition 1.1. Let (X, T) be a topological space with topology T. subset of X, the collection If Y is a T Y = {Y U U T} is a topology

More information

STABILITY AND PARADOX IN ALGORITHMIC LOGIC

STABILITY AND PARADOX IN ALGORITHMIC LOGIC STABILITY AND PARADOX IN ALGORITHMIC LOGIC WAYNE AITKEN, JEFFREY A. BARRETT Abstract. Algorithmic logic is the logic of basic statements concerning algorithms and the algorithmic rules of deduction between

More information

Counting. Andreas Klappenecker

Counting. Andreas Klappenecker Counting Andreas Klappenecker Counting k = 0; for(int i=1; i

More information

Submodularity of Minimum-Cost Spanning Tree Games

Submodularity of Minimum-Cost Spanning Tree Games Submodularity of Minimum-Cost Spanning Tree Games Masayuki Kobayashi Yoshio Okamoto Abstract We give a necessary condition and a sufficient condition for a minimum-cost spanning tree game introduced by

More information

Cardinality Lectures

Cardinality Lectures Cardinality Lectures Enrique Treviño March 8, 014 1 Definition of cardinality The cardinality of a set is a measure of the size of a set. When a set A is finite, its cardinality is the number of elements

More information

A GRAPH FROM THE VIEWPOINT OF ALGEBRAIC TOPOLOGY

A GRAPH FROM THE VIEWPOINT OF ALGEBRAIC TOPOLOGY A GRAPH FROM THE VIEWPOINT OF ALGEBRAIC TOPOLOGY KARL L. STRATOS Abstract. The conventional method of describing a graph as a pair (V, E), where V and E repectively denote the sets of vertices and edges,

More information

arxiv: v4 [math.co] 25 Apr 2010

arxiv: v4 [math.co] 25 Apr 2010 QUIVERS OF FINITE MUTATION TYPE AND SKEW-SYMMETRIC MATRICES arxiv:0905.3613v4 [math.co] 25 Apr 2010 AHMET I. SEVEN Abstract. Quivers of finite mutation type are certain directed graphs that first arised

More information

Utility Maximization

Utility Maximization Utility Maximization Mark Dean Lecture Notes for Spring 2015 Behavioral Economics - Brown University 1 Lecture 1 1.1 Introduction The first topic we are going to cover in the course isn t going to seem

More information

Topology Homework 3. Section Section 3.3. Samuel Otten

Topology Homework 3. Section Section 3.3. Samuel Otten Topology Homework 3 Section 3.1 - Section 3.3 Samuel Otten 3.1 (1) Proposition. The intersection of finitely many open sets is open and the union of finitely many closed sets is closed. Proof. Note that

More information

Revolutionaries and Spies

Revolutionaries and Spies Revolutionaries and Spies arxiv:1106.3838v2 [math.co] 6 Aug 2012 David Howard Department of Mathematics Colgate University Hamilton, NY 13346, U.S.A. Clifford Smyth Department of Mathematics and Statistics

More information

DO NOT RE-DISTRIBUTE THIS SOLUTION FILE

DO NOT RE-DISTRIBUTE THIS SOLUTION FILE Professor Kindred Math 104, Graph Theory Homework 2 Solutions February 7, 2013 Introduction to Graph Theory, West Section 1.2: 26, 38, 42 Section 1.3: 14, 18 Section 2.1: 26, 29, 30 DO NOT RE-DISTRIBUTE

More information

Topology I Test 1 Solutions October 13, 2008

Topology I Test 1 Solutions October 13, 2008 Topology I Test 1 Solutions October 13, 2008 1. Do FIVE of the following: (a) Give a careful definition of connected. A topological space X is connected if for any two sets A and B such that A B = X, we

More information

A Vizing-like theorem for union vertex-distinguishing edge coloring

A Vizing-like theorem for union vertex-distinguishing edge coloring A Vizing-like theorem for union vertex-distinguishing edge coloring Nicolas Bousquet, Antoine Dailly, Éric Duchêne, Hamamache Kheddouci, Aline Parreau Abstract We introduce a variant of the vertex-distinguishing

More information

MTAEA Convexity and Quasiconvexity

MTAEA Convexity and Quasiconvexity School of Economics, Australian National University February 19, 2010 Convex Combinations and Convex Sets. Definition. Given any finite collection of points x 1,..., x m R n, a point z R n is said to be

More information

CHAPTER 8. Copyright Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.

CHAPTER 8. Copyright Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. CHAPTER 8 RELATIONS Copyright Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. SECTION 8.3 Equivalence Relations Copyright Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. The Relation Induced by a Partition 3 The Relation

More information

Massachusetts Institute of Technology Department of Electrical Engineering and Computer Science Algorithms For Inference Fall 2014

Massachusetts Institute of Technology Department of Electrical Engineering and Computer Science Algorithms For Inference Fall 2014 Massachusetts Institute of Technology Department of Electrical Engineering and Computer Science 6.438 Algorithms For Inference Fall 2014 Recitation-6: Hardness of Inference Contents 1 NP-Hardness Part-II

More information

Extremal Graph Theory: Turán s Theorem

Extremal Graph Theory: Turán s Theorem Bridgewater State University Virtual Commons - Bridgewater State University Honors Program Theses and Projects Undergraduate Honors Program 5-9-07 Extremal Graph Theory: Turán s Theorem Vincent Vascimini

More information

Sharp lower bound for the total number of matchings of graphs with given number of cut edges

Sharp lower bound for the total number of matchings of graphs with given number of cut edges South Asian Journal of Mathematics 2014, Vol. 4 ( 2 ) : 107 118 www.sajm-online.com ISSN 2251-1512 RESEARCH ARTICLE Sharp lower bound for the total number of matchings of graphs with given number of cut

More information

Assignment 4 Solutions of graph problems

Assignment 4 Solutions of graph problems Assignment 4 Solutions of graph problems 1. Let us assume that G is not a cycle. Consider the maximal path in the graph. Let the end points of the path be denoted as v 1, v k respectively. If either of

More information

{ 1} Definitions. 10. Extremal graph theory. Problem definition Paths and cycles Complete subgraphs

{ 1} Definitions. 10. Extremal graph theory. Problem definition Paths and cycles Complete subgraphs Problem definition Paths and cycles Complete subgraphs 10. Extremal graph theory 10.1. Definitions Let us examine the following forbidden subgraph problems: At most how many edges are in a graph of order

More information

The Game Chromatic Number of Some Classes of Graphs

The Game Chromatic Number of Some Classes of Graphs The Game Chromatic Number of Some Classes of Graphs Casper Joseph Destacamento 1, Andre Dominic Rodriguez 1 and Leonor Aquino-Ruivivar 1,* 1 Mathematics Department, De La Salle University *leonorruivivar@dlsueduph

More information

Topological properties of convex sets

Topological properties of convex sets Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences Ec 181 KC Border Convex Analysis and Economic Theory Winter 2018 Topic 5: Topological properties of convex sets 5.1 Interior and closure of convex sets Let

More information

Bounded subsets of topological vector spaces

Bounded subsets of topological vector spaces Chapter 2 Bounded subsets of topological vector spaces In this chapter we will study the notion of bounded set in any t.v.s. and analyzing some properties which will be useful in the following and especially

More information

Potential Bisections of Large Degree

Potential Bisections of Large Degree Potential Bisections of Large Degree Stephen G Hartke and Tyler Seacrest Department of Mathematics, University of Nebraska, Lincoln, NE 68588-0130 {hartke,s-tseacre1}@mathunledu June 6, 010 Abstract A

More information

Chapter 3. Set Theory. 3.1 What is a Set?

Chapter 3. Set Theory. 3.1 What is a Set? Chapter 3 Set Theory 3.1 What is a Set? A set is a well-defined collection of objects called elements or members of the set. Here, well-defined means accurately and unambiguously stated or described. Any

More information

On the number of distinct directions of planes determined by n points in R 3

On the number of distinct directions of planes determined by n points in R 3 On the number of distinct directions of planes determined by n points in R 3 Rom Pinchasi August 27, 2007 Abstract We show that any set of n points in R 3, that is not contained in a plane, determines

More information

Choice under Social Constraints

Choice under Social Constraints Choice under Social Constraints T.C.A Madhav Raghavan January 28, 2011 Abstract Agents choose a best element from the available set. But the available set may itself depend on the choices of other agents.

More information

ROUGH MEMBERSHIP FUNCTIONS: A TOOL FOR REASONING WITH UNCERTAINTY

ROUGH MEMBERSHIP FUNCTIONS: A TOOL FOR REASONING WITH UNCERTAINTY ALGEBRAIC METHODS IN LOGIC AND IN COMPUTER SCIENCE BANACH CENTER PUBLICATIONS, VOLUME 28 INSTITUTE OF MATHEMATICS POLISH ACADEMY OF SCIENCES WARSZAWA 1993 ROUGH MEMBERSHIP FUNCTIONS: A TOOL FOR REASONING

More information

Matching Theory. Figure 1: Is this graph bipartite?

Matching Theory. Figure 1: Is this graph bipartite? Matching Theory 1 Introduction A matching M of a graph is a subset of E such that no two edges in M share a vertex; edges which have this property are called independent edges. A matching M is said to

More information

A NOTE ON THE NUMBER OF DOMINATING SETS OF A GRAPH

A NOTE ON THE NUMBER OF DOMINATING SETS OF A GRAPH A NOTE ON THE NUMBER OF DOMINATING SETS OF A GRAPH STEPHAN WAGNER Abstract. In a recent article by Bród and Skupień, sharp upper and lower bounds for the number of dominating sets in a tree were determined.

More information

On Soft Topological Linear Spaces

On Soft Topological Linear Spaces Republic of Iraq Ministry of Higher Education and Scientific Research University of AL-Qadisiyah College of Computer Science and Formation Technology Department of Mathematics On Soft Topological Linear

More information

Comment on Strategic Information Management Under Leakage in a. Supply Chain

Comment on Strategic Information Management Under Leakage in a. Supply Chain Comment on Strategic Information Management Under Leakage in a Supply Chain Lin Tian 1 School of International Business Administration, Shanghai University of Finance and Economics, 00433 Shanghai, China,

More information

Discrete mathematics , Fall Instructor: prof. János Pach

Discrete mathematics , Fall Instructor: prof. János Pach Discrete mathematics 2016-2017, Fall Instructor: prof. János Pach - covered material - Lecture 1. Counting problems To read: [Lov]: 1.2. Sets, 1.3. Number of subsets, 1.5. Sequences, 1.6. Permutations,

More information

EDGE MAXIMAL GRAPHS CONTAINING NO SPECIFIC WHEELS. Jordan Journal of Mathematics and Statistics (JJMS) 8(2), 2015, pp I.

EDGE MAXIMAL GRAPHS CONTAINING NO SPECIFIC WHEELS. Jordan Journal of Mathematics and Statistics (JJMS) 8(2), 2015, pp I. EDGE MAXIMAL GRAPHS CONTAINING NO SPECIFIC WHEELS M.S.A. BATAINEH (1), M.M.M. JARADAT (2) AND A.M.M. JARADAT (3) A. Let k 4 be a positive integer. Let G(n; W k ) denote the class of graphs on n vertices

More information

Group Secret Key Generation Algorithms

Group Secret Key Generation Algorithms Group Secret Key Generation Algorithms Chunxuan Ye and Alex Reznik InterDigital Communications Corporation King of Prussia, PA 9406 Email: {Chunxuan.Ye, Alex.Reznik}@interdigital.com arxiv:cs/07024v [cs.it]

More information

On the number of quasi-kernels in digraphs

On the number of quasi-kernels in digraphs On the number of quasi-kernels in digraphs Gregory Gutin Department of Computer Science Royal Holloway, University of London Egham, Surrey, TW20 0EX, UK gutin@dcs.rhbnc.ac.uk Khee Meng Koh Department of

More information

On Sequential Topogenic Graphs

On Sequential Topogenic Graphs Int. J. Contemp. Math. Sciences, Vol. 5, 2010, no. 36, 1799-1805 On Sequential Topogenic Graphs Bindhu K. Thomas, K. A. Germina and Jisha Elizabath Joy Research Center & PG Department of Mathematics Mary

More information

CPS 102: Discrete Mathematics. Quiz 3 Date: Wednesday November 30, Instructor: Bruce Maggs NAME: Prob # Score. Total 60

CPS 102: Discrete Mathematics. Quiz 3 Date: Wednesday November 30, Instructor: Bruce Maggs NAME: Prob # Score. Total 60 CPS 102: Discrete Mathematics Instructor: Bruce Maggs Quiz 3 Date: Wednesday November 30, 2011 NAME: Prob # Score Max Score 1 10 2 10 3 10 4 10 5 10 6 10 Total 60 1 Problem 1 [10 points] Find a minimum-cost

More information

SEQUENCES, MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION, AND RECURSION

SEQUENCES, MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION, AND RECURSION CHAPTER 5 SEQUENCES, MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION, AND RECURSION Alessandro Artale UniBZ - http://www.inf.unibz.it/ artale/ SECTION 5.5 Application: Correctness of Algorithms Copyright Cengage Learning. All

More information

SPERNER S LEMMA MOOR XU

SPERNER S LEMMA MOOR XU SPERNER S LEMMA MOOR XU Abstract. Is it possible to dissect a square into an odd number of triangles of equal area? This question was first answered by Paul Monsky in 970, and the solution requires elements

More information

Parameterized graph separation problems

Parameterized graph separation problems Parameterized graph separation problems Dániel Marx Department of Computer Science and Information Theory, Budapest University of Technology and Economics Budapest, H-1521, Hungary, dmarx@cs.bme.hu Abstract.

More information

Abstract. A graph G is perfect if for every induced subgraph H of G, the chromatic number of H is equal to the size of the largest clique of H.

Abstract. A graph G is perfect if for every induced subgraph H of G, the chromatic number of H is equal to the size of the largest clique of H. Abstract We discuss a class of graphs called perfect graphs. After defining them and getting intuition with a few simple examples (and one less simple example), we present a proof of the Weak Perfect Graph

More information

EC 521 MATHEMATICAL METHODS FOR ECONOMICS. Lecture 2: Convex Sets

EC 521 MATHEMATICAL METHODS FOR ECONOMICS. Lecture 2: Convex Sets EC 51 MATHEMATICAL METHODS FOR ECONOMICS Lecture : Convex Sets Murat YILMAZ Boğaziçi University In this section, we focus on convex sets, separating hyperplane theorems and Farkas Lemma. And as an application

More information

REVIEW OF FUZZY SETS

REVIEW OF FUZZY SETS REVIEW OF FUZZY SETS CONNER HANSEN 1. Introduction L. A. Zadeh s paper Fuzzy Sets* [1] introduces the concept of a fuzzy set, provides definitions for various fuzzy set operations, and proves several properties

More information

Topology and Topological Spaces

Topology and Topological Spaces Topology and Topological Spaces Mathematical spaces such as vector spaces, normed vector spaces (Banach spaces), and metric spaces are generalizations of ideas that are familiar in R or in R n. For example,

More information

On Conditional Covering Problem

On Conditional Covering Problem On Conditional Covering Problem S. Balasubramanian, S. Harini, and C. Pandu Rangan Department of Computer Science and Engineering, IIT Madras, Chennai India 600036 balas,harini@cse.iitm.ernet.in,rangan@iitm.ernet.in

More information